The Individualist Constitution
Libertarian legal superstar Randy Barnett challenges conservative judicial orthodoxy.


In 2012 Chief Justice John Roberts led the U.S. Supreme Court in upholding the constitutionality of the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act. "It is not our job," Roberts wrote in National Federation of Independent Business v. Sebelius, "to protect the people from the consequences of their political choices." With those deferential words, Obamacare was saved from legal destruction.
Most conservatives today remain outraged by Roberts' opinion. But according to Georgetown law professor Randy Barnett, one of the architects of the legal challenge to Obamacare, those conservatives don't really understand what it is they're railing against. In that case, Barnett writes in his new book, Our Republican Constitution: Securing the Liberty and Sovereignty of We the People, "the chickens of the conservative commitment to judicial restraint [came] home to roost." For far too long, Barnett maintains, too many legal conservatives, from John Roberts on down, have championed judicial deference to majority rule at the expense of the judiciary's duty to enforce the Constitution and act as a check against the other branches of government. Conservative legal orthodoxy itself, in other words, played a central role in allowing Obamacare to survive.
Barnett is now on a mission to upend that orthodoxy. "The Obamacare decision had a very galvanizing and chastening impact on conservatives generally, and I believe caused them to begin to rethink this reflexive acceptance of a progressive concept of judicial restraint," Barnett says. "This book is intended to offer my proposed approach to the appropriate role of judges going forward."
Barnett, a professor of legal theory at Georgetown University Law Center and the author of nine previous books, including Restoring the Lost Constitution: The Presumption of Liberty, spoke with Senior Editor Damon Root in February about the republican Constitution, the specter of judicial activism, the legacy of Justice Antonin Scalia, and why he worries that "winter is coming" to the U.S. Supreme Court.
reason: The title of your new book is Our Republican Constitution. You say that you are using the term republican in a non-partisan manner. How are you using the term?
Randy Barnett: The thesis of the book is that there are two different approaches to the Constitution, the republican one and the democratic one. They're each based on different conceptions of "We the People." If you take "We the People" as a group, and you're concerned with "We the People" governing, then the only way that the will of the people can govern is by majority rule. So then anything that gets in the way of majority rule is suspect and potentially illegitimate. Which includes judges getting in the way. Judges are not accountable, they're not elected, and if they get in the way of the will of the people there is something wrong there. That's the democratic Constitution.
If you take "We the People" as individuals, as I believe the Declaration of Independence does, then the purpose of government, according to the Declaration, is to secure the rights of "We the People," each and every one of us. Then government is the servant of the people, and the function of judges—who are also servants of the people—is to fairly adjudicate disputes between members of the sovereign people and their servants. People as a group yields completely different judges than people as individuals. "We the People" as individuals yields a republican Constitution and in the book I maintain that the Constitution we have is a republican Constitution.
reason: You stress the idea that the rights of the American people predate the existence of the American government. Why?
Barnett: The Declaration of Independence says that all persons are created equal and they are endowed by their creator with certain inalienable rights. So the Declaration says, first comes rights and then comes government to secure these rights. That is the republican vision that led to the U.S. Constitution.
reason: What role do the Reconstruction Amendments—the 13th, 14th, and 15th Amendments—play in your conception of the Constitution?
Barnett: The initial Constitution, though it was republican and though it was not democratic, was highly imperfect. It left democratic rule at the state level free enough to impose slavery on some members of their populations. Eventually, as everyone knows, this led to intense conflict and a new anti-slavery Republican Party, and eventually a Civil War, finally culminating in that Republican Party passing amendments to the Constitution that did not make the Constitution perfect, but did make it much more republican. It now protected individuals from majorities in their states where previously those protections were very, very few in the Constitution.
reason: You're closely associated with the legal philosophy known as originalism, which says that the Constitution should be interpreted according to its original meaning. What's wrong with the idea of viewing the Constitution as a living document, or at least as a document that's flexible enough to adapt and change with the times?
Barnett: The written Constitution is the law that governs those who govern us. Those who are being governed by that law should not be able themselves to change it without going through the amendment process any more than we can change the laws that are governing us just because we don't like them. A written Constitution is simply a means to protect the rights and powers retained by the sovereign people. You have to jump through some amendment hoops before the government can expand its powers. They cannot do it on their own. That's all originalism says.
reason: You envision the courts playing a robust role in enforcing the terms of the Constitution. What do you say to the charge that your approach will end up giving judges the license to engage in judicial activism?
Barnett: Judicial activism is a pejorative used by people to describe judges striking down laws that they shouldn't strike down. Almost no one believes that judges should never strike down any law. So striking down a law that ought to be struck down is not judicial activism. I'm only calling for judges to invalidate laws that are unconstitutional, and therefore I do not favor judicial activism. But I do favor what's called "judicial engagement," which means that judges should not be passive and should not be upholding laws that are unconstitutional. And by unconstitutional here I mean beyond the just powers of government, as the Declaration says.
reason: When we talk about constitutional law, it's common to talk in terms of rights. Did the government violate my right to free speech, did the government violate my right to keep and bear arms, etc. But you spend much more time in this book on the issue of government powers. Why is that?
Barnett: One of the purposes of this book is to refocus our attention on the scope of government powers and move away from this discussion of rights. As you know, I've done a lot of work on the Ninth Amendment ["The enumeration in the Constitution of certain rights shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people"], but I never thought it was the first, best option for judges to identify unenumerated rights and then enforce them. That was only something that should be done in our current constitutional regime in which certain rights are separated out for special protection; I believe others should be added as well. But I believe the first, best option is to hold government to its just powers. We shouldn't be focusing most of our attention—and neither should judges—on what our rights are. We should be focusing our attention on what are the just powers of government and asking whether government is acting within those just powers, whenever it is restricting the liberty of the people as generally understood.
Now, the liberty of the people does not include the liberty to rape, murder, or rob people; that's not liberty. That's what a classical liberal would call license, or unjust conduct. But if you're not doing any of those things, if you're going about your business and now government wants to restrict your liberties, then it needs to do so only within the limits of its just powers. The attention of this book is on what are the just powers of government, and how does the U.S. Constitution limit governmental powers, and why are those limits good for liberty without judges specifically protecting rights per se?
reason: On the state level, doesn't that still raise the question of what rights are protected by the 14th Amendment, either via its Privileges or Immunities Clause or via its Due Process Clause? How should federal courts go about holding states to their just powers?
Barnett: I agree it's somewhat more difficult at the state level. The Privileges or Immunities Clause is really no more difficult to understand than the Ninth Amendment. It's a reference to the retained liberties of the people as well as certain additional special protections that are enumerated in the text of the Constitution that formerly had been only applied to the federal government. Identifying the privileges or immunities is not all that difficult. What makes states somewhat more difficult is figuring out what are the just powers of states. The Congress has specific, enumerated powers, so you have a list you can consult. As long as they are exercising one of those powers it's constitutional. States have general powers. So then you need a theory of what those powers are. Now, these are unenumerated powers. Unenumerated things are more uncertain than enumerated things. But general powers were never thought to be unlimited powers. Unlimited power is tyranny. Arbitrary and irrational rule is tyranny. And no small-r republican thought states had that kind of power.
I talk a lot in the book about irrationality and arbitrariness and how there was always objection to irrational and arbitrary laws. The debate then is over what is the exact scope of government power, what are the appropriate state purposes. And there is a fundamental agreement, a widespread consensus on some of that, which we can summarize as health and safety laws. Any laws that are meant to protect the health and safety of the public would be within the proper province of state governments.
reason: What do you say to those who maintain that the states actually have very broad powers to regulate economic affairs, including the passage of what you or I might consider to be "irrational" legislation that harms economic liberty?
Barnett: I don't think there are very many people who would expressly say that states have the power to pass irrational and arbitrary laws of any kind. The Supreme Court has never said that. In fact, it's denied it. I think that the Constitution is not perfectly libertarian, and it is constitutional for states to regulate economic liberty in ways that we libertarians might find counterproductive and bad. That doesn't necessarily make them irrational and arbitrary. The Constitution provides an outer boundary that is more libertarian than the one the courts currently enforce, but may not be perfectly libertarian.
I would also stress that libertarians do believe in the reasonable regulation of liberty. Libertarians have nothing against contract law. Contract law is an elaborate body of doctrine meant to regulate the making and enforcing of contracts. Libertarians do not object to property law, which is an elaborate body of doctrine related to the acquisition, ownership, possession, and disposition of property. Or tort law. These are all bodies of law that regulate the exercise of liberty and distinguish between rightful conduct and wrongful conduct.
reason: Many conservatives are critical of substantive due process, or the use of the Due Process Clause to protect substantive rights from government regulation. You're also somewhat critical of it in this book. But at the same time you maintain that judges should use the Due Process Clauses to protect substantive rights in certain cases. Could you explain that?
Barnett: Substantive due process was a phrase made up to criticize the Court for using the Due Process Clause in certain ways. It was meant as a pejorative, like judicial activism. It was meant to be contradictory. Substantive due process is a contradiction in terms; procedural due process is a redundancy. So it was always a pejorative term. Modern substantive due process is objectionable because it relies on judges to distinguish between liberties they find to be fundamental and liberties they find not to be fundamental, and to protect the former and not protect the latter.
The Due Process Clause is about the application of statutes that purport to be laws to individual persons. It's part of the due process of law that an individual person can challenge whether a law is within the just powers of the government to impose on them and is properly a law. And they ought to be able to do so before a neutral tribunal, which is what is provided by the judiciary. So in that sense judges should be able to say whether a law is within the just powers of government, and they're going to have to look at the substance of the law—not just the way it was passed—in order to assess that.
reason: In other words, being able to go to court to vindicate your rights is part of what the due process of law covers?
Barnett: One way of looking at this is when you bring a First Amendment claim in court, there's no reason why it's not a "substantive due process" claim. It's part of the process of law that individuals can go to court and challenge a statute that's being applied to them because it violates the First Amendment. We just think of that as a First Amendment case, but the challenge that's taking place in court is part of the due process of law. And to handle that challenge you need to look at the substance of the law to see if it violates the First Amendment.
reason: Your previous books have been published by academic presses and written largely for scholarly audiences. This book reads more like a call to arms. Who is your intended audience here?
Barnett: This book starts off by talking about my experience in challenging Obamacare. And I do believe the Supreme Court's decision in Obamacare represented a legal-cultural inflection point for the conservative and libertarian legal movement. Up until that time, those of us who argued for the kind of judicial engagement we've been discussing were clearly the minority view within the conservative legal movement. The Obamacare decision had a very galvanizing and chastening impact on conservatives generally, and I believe caused them to begin to rethink this reflexive acceptance of a progressive concept of judicial restraint.
Now exactly where that rethinking takes them is an open question. This book is intended to offer my proposed approach to the appropriate role of judges going forward. It's directed more specifically at conservatives than the left. In the past my academic writings have probably been more aimed at the progressive mainstream of legal academia, whereas this book is really more aimed at conservatives—and libertarians, because I don't think libertarians fully understand what they ought to be for, either.
That's my target, therefore it has a certain stridency my other writings haven't had. I presented the book to a seminar here at Georgetown and one of the students reasonably replied that as a progressive he found the rhetoric a little bit off-putting. And I replied, "It wasn't written for you." It was written for people who already agree on some of these things but have a different view of judges. And I think their different view of judges has always been based on a different view of "We the People" and popular sovereignty. It's a book that goes back to first principles in order to expose people to this other vision of popular sovereignty.
reason: You just referred to some conservatives having a "progressive concept of judicial restraint." Lots of conservatives probably think judicial restraint is a bedrock conservative principle. What does progressivism have to do with it?
Barnett: This book is primarily a narrative. It's a story that starts at the beginning and takes us to the present. And a very important chapter in that story, and in my book, is about how the progressives changed our view of the Constitution as well as our view of the role of judges. They changed it from a republican Constitution, where judges were considered to be guardians of the rights of the people, to a democratic Constitution, where judges are problematic because they thwart the will of the people and therefore should exercise their power of judicial review with restraint.
By the way, the phrase "the power of judicial review" was relatively unknown prior to the 20th century. Prior to the 20th century, prior to the rise of progressivism, there was simply a judicial duty to enforce the law. And the Constitution being higher law, any inferior law such as a statute that was in conflict with the higher law was invalid. Where did "the power of judicial review" come from, as opposed to the judicial duty to follow the law? It came from, I believe, the idea that duties are obligatory; you have to do it. But powers are discretionary. By shifting from the idea of duty to follow the law to the power of judicial review, [progressives] introduced the notion of judicial discretion and judicial restraint precisely to get judges out of the business of protecting the liberties of the people from progressive state legislatures and then a progressive Congress, in the form of the New Deal Congress. So this was a calculated political strategy. And modern political conservatives were all educated by progressives of various kinds, and the debate on the Court after the New Deal was between the restraint progressives and the activist progressives. Conservatives tend to line up with the restraint progressives. The book tells this story in some detail.
reason: In your view, what Supreme Court decisions reflect the judicial duty properly applied?
Barnett: I spend a great deal of time talking about the lower court decision in Williamson v. Lee Optical, which was called Lee Optical v. Oklahoma. In the lower court decision, which was a three-judge panel, it evaluated a restriction on the practice of selling eyeglasses in Oklahoma. Lee Optical was a company that operated basically like LensCrafters does today: You could go into the store to get new glasses and they would figure out what your prescription was by putting your glasses in a lensometer, and they would make you a new pair of glasses. The legislature basically outlawed what we would think of as LensCrafters in favor of sending everybody to ophthalmologists and optometrists, denying opticians the right to pursue this occupation. The lower court judges said that this was unconstitutional because it was irrational and arbitrary, and they took evidence, they heard argument, they heard witnesses, and after evaluating the evidence in a lengthy opinion they explained why this was irrational and arbitrary.
It then went to the Supreme Court and the Supreme Court said, "Forget all the evidence. Forget realistically assessing the law. As long as we can imagine a reason why the legislature might have done these things, even if there's no evidence that's why they did it, it's constitutional enough for us." I think people should look at that [lower court] decision as a model of what judges are capable of doing.
reason: You were an adviser to Rand Paul's presidential campaign. Now that Paul has dropped out of the 2016 race, are there any remaining presidential candidates who align with your legal views?
Barnett: I'm not advising any other campaigns, and by the time this interview appears we may know who the Republican nominee is going to be. Libertarians—and conservatives also—may be put to some very hard choices about who they should support in the next election.
reason: The recent death of Justice Antonin Scalia has thrown the future of the Supreme Court into doubt. You got to know Scalia personally and also argued before him in Gonzales v. Raich, where you represented medical marijuana patients in a federalism challenge to the Controlled Substances Act. Can you say a few words about Scalia and his influence on the law?
Barnett: I first met Justice Scalia when I was a research fellow at the University of Chicago. He was a contracts professor. The next time I saw him was when I argued the Raich case. He was my toughest questioner that morning and he ruled against us. I must admit that I was bitterly disappointed by his stance. I wrote a rather strident article condemning his approach, called "Scalia's Infidelity," in the Cincinnati Law Review. After I came to Georgetown I got to know him professionally. We never became social friends but I got to know him in a variety of venues.
He visited my small seminar to talk about his new book, and I introduced him at various talks at Georgetown. And I grew very fond of him. I also taught constitutional law and I taught his opinions. I came to respect his concurring opinion in the Raich case. I don't have a very high opinion of Justice [John Paul] Stevens' majority opinion, but I think Justice Scalia's concurring opinion is quite well-reasoned and only makes a single assumption that changes the outcome. And that is whether we were entitled to a meaningful hearing on whether this prohibition on medical marijuana was essential to a broader regulatory scheme. He adopted the judicial deference and restraint approach, and once he did that the outcome was determined. But the structure of his argument was actually pretty good. So I got to know him, I got to respect him, and then upon his passing I realized I had actually grown to like him. I hadn't realized that I had grown some affection for him.
His legacy is complicated. He had a huge impact on the way the Supreme Court does its job. When he came in, the Supreme Court was anti-textualist. It paid scant attention to the text; it pretty much did whatever it felt like. This was exemplified by his sole dissent in Morrison v. Olson about the independent counsel law [allowing for investigations of public officials to be conducted by "special prosecutors" who do not answer to the president]. It was an 8–1 decision. Chief Justice Rehnquist wrote the majority. Justice Scalia had just come on the Court when he dissented and questioned [the law's] constitutionality based on first principles and separation of powers. He predicted very bad results as a result of this law and his prediction proved prescient. Not because he was such a great prognosticator but because he was following the principles of the Constitution.
We've gone from that decision in the 1980s to the Heller case in 2008 in which now, representing the majority, Scalia writes a comprehensively originalist opinion restoring to the Constitution an entire amendment in the Bill of Rights, the Second Amendment right to keep and bear arms. Even the dissenters in that case, as exemplified by Justice Stevens' dissent, were speaking wholly in originalist terms. Nine justices all talking about original meaning. That's a sea change, and he is responsible for that sea change.
reason: You've been a constitutional scholar and litigator for three decades. From where you stand now, are you optimistic or pessimistic about the future of the law?
Barnett: It's going to depend on who replaces Justice Scalia and who replaces other justices that will inevitably retire. If they're replaced by progressives who believe in a living Constitution then we're in for a very long winter. Winter is coming, Damon.
Things have been moving in the direction of originalism, things have been moving in the direction of limited government in the courts—very slowly, very incrementally, but it has been moving forward. And we're winning the intellectual battle outside the Court, which has started to have an effect inside the Court. But ultimately who gets to be on the Court is a political matter that gets to be decided by an elected president and an elected Senate. If the elections go the wrong way, or the president is insufficiently aware of these issues, or delegates this decision to the wrong people, then we can be in for a very bad time.
This article originally appeared in print under the headline "The Individualist Constitution."
Editor's Note: As of February 29, 2024, commenting privileges on reason.com posts are limited to Reason Plus subscribers. Past commenters are grandfathered in for a temporary period. Subscribe here to preserve your ability to comment. Your Reason Plus subscription also gives you an ad-free version of reason.com, along with full access to the digital edition and archives of Reason magazine. We request that comments be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment and ban commenters for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Nice article.
But at this point in time if Hillary wins, what difference will it make?
The game will effectively be over, and the progressive court will forever remove the concept of inalienable rights, replacing them with a need forevermore to ask the government "may I do this" and to always comply when the government says "you shall do this".
It's already over. Both T and C will nominate living constitution judges. The only issue now is a)where is Valley Forge and b)how do we prepare for next year
The highly partisan D/R structure has created -- 100% of current justices from Harvard/Yale/Columbia (and only one is Columbia). 100% Catholic/Jewish (relevant because both religions legal traditions actually derive from both religions lack of tradition regarding separation). All but one Federal Appeals court background (and mostly DC circuit). All vetted solely on political suitability on one or two issues. The consequence is a court that is extremely predictable in how it will rule and what cases it will take. The court isn't a court anymore. It is an extension of politics - and predictable voterbase politics at that. Promoting even superficial diversity on the above - by helping to break the existing bipartisan consensus on them - is probably easy to do for libertarian-leaners and might at least provide some hope for future legal cases.
More productive is to recognize that the judiciary is not the next battleground. I like the Repeal Amendment idea - to get the states back in the battle.
I do agree. I think a convention of the states is inevitable.
I am totally for anything that will curtail the runaway power of the U.S. and empower the States to reclaim their rightful position in that relationship; however, what exactly do you think 2/3 of State legislatures are likely to agree on?
As for a Constitutional Convention, that could be a real Pandora's Box depending on which side has the clout to prevail, but I agree it is inevitable [or we just continue to allow government agencies like the Department of Education to micro-manage us into dystopia, and for Federal judges to let them have their way].
Indeed, a good interview with an interesting subject.
The unenumerated powers of state governments is a huge loophole. Supposing the best at the federal level, with a court ready to roll back even the New Deal and all the rest of the nanny state, you'd then have a crazy quilt of state powers, some being worse than the federal powers now, some being as close to libertarian as anyone could hope for. How long would that last? How long before nanny states would find some way to force the federal government to help them, to enable even worse abuses?
If the federals could be rolled back to, say, pre-Civil War powers, and individual states could be restrained to not violate just the enumerated bill of rights, then nanny states would be doomed by their own excesses, and the market of 50 states would rein in the worst abuses. But what would prevent the nanny states from getting bailouts from a sympathetic nanny federal government which couldn't do those things itself because a proper judiciary was limiting it to its federally enumerated powers?
It would still be better than what we have now, but limiting the federal government to its truly enumerated powers is just a pipe dream of the silliest sort.
To make it clear, when I say roll back the federals to pre-Civil War powers, I don't mean repeal the 13th, 14th, and 15th amendments. I mean before the federal budget expanded so much, before it grabbed so many domestic powers under the flag of fighting an insurrection, and well before progressives used that war expansion in peacetime. Of course the Fed would have to go away, that's not an enumerated power, but I explicitly do not mean without the income tax or prohibition amendments, because those were handled the constitutional way, as much as they disgust me.
The more that courts feel empowered to overturn democratic legislation, the more politicized court nominations will be. We have been able to depend on the courts to defend free speech because it enjoys residual support on both sides of the political spectrum, but the broader the political powers of courts, the more likely are they to be taken over by political muscle-men. (I am put in mind of Communist intellectuals who are surprised that when all roads to success and power in a Party state go through the Party, the Party gradually is taken over by careerists.)
It seems to me the power of the courts are broader presently than they would be if guided by the principles Barnett advocates and court appts under progs are nothing if not political. Hell, FDR's admin is noted for his stacking of the SCOTUS, a practice continued to this day.
If a judge's job description emphasized the government is always guilty until proven innocent, that problem wouldn't exist.
Republican or democratic constitution wouldn't matter. Judicial nominations wouldn't matter. Insist that the burden of proof is on the government, use strict scrutiny, require unanimous votes to affirm government rules and policies.
Of course that will never happen.
We have been able to depend on the courts to defend free speech because it enjoys residual support on both sides of the political spectrum
I'm pretty sure I saw each and every Dem Senator vote for an attempt to overturn the Citizens United decision...
Roberts thinks his job is to protect legislators from the consequences of their poorly written and conceived legislation. He'll just rewrite it from the bench.
"We the people" is from the preamble to the constitution, not the declaration of independence.
If you take "We the People" as a group, and you're concerned with "We the People" governing, then the only way that the will of the people can govern is by majority rule.
Is it really even possible to take 'we the people' in its original context and construe it as meaning majority rule? I mean, honestly? The government established by the founders was not majoritarian. It was very Republican. Congress wasn't even democratically elected. The electoral college picked the president. Deference to the legislatures as representatives of the will of the people depends upon a level of democracy that came later.
The purpose of the constitution is to limit the government, and to protect the inalienable rights of the minority from the whims of the majority.
SCOTUS defers to Congress. Congress defers to tge Executive. King George we missed you! Please tax our tea.
The problem was the conservatives gave up on winning the battle for interpreting the Constitution. They decided that it was easier to say "the Constitution doesn't right every wrong" in response to judicial activism than to argue against the merits of the decision. The entire idea of "judicial activism" ceded the field to liberals. The Warren Court was not "activist". It was wrong. The problem wasn't that they were overruling legislatures. The problem was they were doing so for the wrong reasons. Somehow that distinction got lost.
I like the cut of Randy's jib.
He's #2 on my list of SCOTUS appointees behind Janice Rogers Brown...
I'm only calling for judges to invalidate laws that are unconstitutional, and therefore I do not favor judicial activism. But I do favor what's called "judicial engagement," which means that judges should not be passive and should not be upholding laws that are unconstitutional.
Seems to me that the Court hides behind judicial restraint when it's really just reluctant to overturn past wrongs.
Whether the Court should disregard the real world consequences of overturning Filburn is the question. In Gonzales v. Raich, they avoided overturning it on the basis of Filburn. From the majority opinion:
"The regulation is squarely within Congress' commerce power because production of the commodity meant for home consumption, be it wheat or marijuana, has a substantial effect on supply and demand in the national market for that commodity."
It was the Court's reluctance to overturn Filburn that led to the mental gymnastics of the ACA decision.
We need to be more specific about the nature of judicial restraint. It would take complete idiots on the Court to disregard the real world consequences of overturning Filburn on the constitutionality of government regulation and the constitutionality of the drug war, but if Filburn needs to be overturned, then that's what we need--a Court that is willing to overturn it despite the real world consequences of doing so.
Isn't that deference to real world consequences often what we're really talking about when we're talking about with terms like originalism, judicial activism, and judicial restraint?
This is the argument that Scalia made. I don't agree with it but it is not unreasonable. The argument is that even if an interpretation is wrong, at some point society and government has come to rely upon it to such a huge degree that overturning it would result in so much disruption that it would create more harm that good. The best example of this is the Commerce Clause. If the courts ever went back to a accurate interpretation of the commerce clause, 75% of what the federal government does would be ended by judicial decree. I like most people on here would see that as a good thing. Scalia and others understandably see some problem with a group of five unelected judges telling the public that everything they thought about government and the constitution is wrong and outlawing most of the what the federal government does overnight and by judicial fiat.
I understand the reluctance to burn down 75% of what the federal government does by judicial decree, too.
I just think we should call it out for what it is so that we can have a discussion with people about what's really at stake here. It isn't really about interpretation--it's about perpetuating the mistakes of the past.
There have been other instances where the consequences of doing the right thing were onerous. The Court was once reluctant to rule properly on something for fear it would destroy the economy of every state south of the Mason-Dixon line. I wish the Court had done the right thing and pulled the rug out from under slavery anyway.
And while the price of pulling the rug out from under federal regulation and the misapplication of the commerce clause might be steep, it's not like suffering the drug war and the ACA is without consequences either. I wish more people understood the argument in terms of the consequences of upholding past mistakes, anyway, rather than seeing the debate as being about philosophical differences in interpretation.
I agree Ken. I was just saying that the other side in this debate are not necessarily unreasonable or enemies of liberty.
But there are so many ways it could be trimmed! Raich could easily have won w/o overturning Wickard. All that had to be said was that the aims of the Controlled Substances Act were the opposite of the agricultural laws at stake with Wickard, so that it would be disingenuous to use the latter as precedent for the former. Or it could've been said that when a state enacts its own regulatory scheme with the same ends in mind as Congress, that Congress's aim in having a comprehensive regulatory scheme is satisfied by the state's good-faith enforcement of its own.
Not only that, but overturning Wickard would not have as broad a consequence as you think. Congress has written into many statutes a requirement that the commerce in question be interstate. For instance, that's how the FFDCA is written. The states have their own parallel pharmacy laws, and the FFDCA includes a presumption of interstate commerce in condemnation proceedings?but it's a presumption that may be rebutted. It is the unusual case where a federal statute is written to apply to anyone in any state, as in the CSA. So even striking down all purely intrastate effects of current federal statutes would not be as jarring as you think. For the most part, state & federal laws are parallel. If the question of interstate commerce came down to the trial court level, hardly any cases would be affected.
"For far too long, Barnett maintains, too many legal conservatives, from John Roberts on down, have championed judicial deference to majority rule"
And in the Obamacare case, Roberts assumed that the relevant majority was a majority of the whole country, not the majorities in those many states which had chosen *not* to have an Obamacare-style system.
So if it's majority-versus-majority, the so-called "judicial deference" people often steal a base and defer to the wrong majority.
That is a great point. The question is whether Roberts had his head so far up his ass he forgot there was a difference between the two majorities.
FTFY. Everyone's fine with judges striking down laws they didn't like. But those same people will scream "JUDISHUL AKTIVIZM!!!!!11!!1" when a law they liked gets stuck down.
I'm surprised he didn't request a trigger warning and a safe space. And a blankie and a binky.
"It is not our job," Roberts wrote in National Federation of Independent Business v. Sebelius, "to protect the people from the consequences of their political choices."
I think people of my generation grew up believing that's exactly what the courts should be doing. Protecting individuals from other people's political choices. What's the point of having a constitution if we're living in a pure democracy?
Brown 1 and Miranda looked like pretty straightforward attempts to ensure individual equal protection. Then came Brown 2 and it became obvious that the court really didn't give a shit about individual rights. After Roe "conservatives" started whining about legislating from the bench and with Sebelius they got what they wanted, but didn't.
As an individual I'm pretty sure I have a right to abortion and gay butt sex. Everything else requires a political consensus it would seem. But great article. Thank you Reason.