The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The Statute Allowing Judges to Appoint Interim U.S. Attorneys is Constitutional
Steve Calabresi's argument that judges cannot make such interim appointments is ultimately unpersuasive, as the Appointments Clause specifically allows Congress to vest such power in the Judiciary.
Leading constitutional law scholar and VC co-blogger Steve Calabresi has posted an interesting analysis of the Attorney General's authority to appoint interim U.S. Attorneys—and of federal judges' authority to step in and make an appointment after the expiration of an interim term. Calabresi argues that the part of the federal statute authorizing judicial appointments (28 U.S.C. § 546(d)) is unconstitutional. I often find Calabresi's analysis of constitutional issues powerful. On this particular issue, however, I disagree. Even proceeding on the originalist and textualist premises Calabresi relies on, his argument is unpersuasive.
Calabresi's argument essentially requires ignoring the text of the Constitution's Appointments Clause, the history and tradition of judicial appointments of interim U.S. Attorneys, and important Supreme Court precedents. Against this backdrop of text, history, and tradition, § 546(d) is constitutional.
In today's post, I focus on this constitutional issue. I hope to follow-up tomorrow with another post on how the statute operates in practice. Calabresi is seemingly correct that, by making repeated interim appointments, a determined Executive can block the ability of judges to make appointments. Thus, even if the statute's judicial appointment authority is constitutional, it may ultimately end up rarely being used.
As the springboard for analyzing the constitutionality of the judicial appointment provision, Calabresi analyzes the recent controversy over Alina Habba's (recently expired)120-day term as Interim U.S. Attorney for the District of New Jersey. Ms. Habba had been acting as the Interim U.S. Attorney while her nomination to become the U.S. Attorney was pending before the Senate. As Ms. Habba's interim term was drawing to a close, the district judges for the District of Jersey entered a terse order declining to extend it. Instead, citing their authority under § 546(d), the judges appointed Ms. Habba's First Assistant (Desiree Leigh Grace) to the interim position. The Trump Administration responded by the President withdrawing Ms. Habba's nomination. And then Attorney General Bondi appointed her to be First Assistant in that U.S. Attorney's Office and also Acting U.S. Attorney for the District for the next 210 days pursuant to the Federal Vacancies Reform Act of 1998, 5 U.S.C. §§ 3345 et seq. Writing on X, Attorney General Bondi explained that "[t]his Department of Justice does not tolerate rogue judges—especially when they threaten the President's core Article II powers." The Attorney General also removed the First Assistant (Ms. Grace) from the interim U.S. Attorney position.
The question of judicial appointments is an important issue, not only in the U.S. Attorney context but also in other areas. To focus the discussion, like Calabresi, I will discuss the Attorney General's appointment authority under § 546 rather than the Federal Vacancies Reform Act, which is apparently a "fallback" position of the Trump Administration. On § 546, Calabresi defends the Attorney General's position by arguing that the part of the statute that the New Jersey judges relied upon to make their appointment is unconstitutional. Here's the text in question:
If an appointment expires under subsection (c)(2) [i.e., under an interim appointment by the Attorney General], the district court for such district may appoint a United States attorney to serve until the vacancy is filled.
28 U.S.C. § 546(d).
Calabresi concedes that versions of this provision "have been in the U.S Code since the Civil War," but notes "they have rarely been invoked" by judges. Nonetheless, the concession of long-standing historical foundation for judicial appointments should give an originalist pause. Calabresi's main argument is that the judicial appointment provision is now unconstitutional under two recent Supreme Court decisions: Seila Law (2020) and Trump v. Wilcox (2025). Under these decisions, contends Calabresi, the power to prosecute is a core "executive Power" under Article II, Section 1. And, accordingly, under these recent decisions, only the Attorney General (acting on behalf of the President) can appoint Interim U.S. Attorneys. In my view, Calabresi conclusion overreads these recent decisions and incorrectly downplays other, controlling Supreme Court precedents.
It will be useful to set the stage for the issue with some historical background about the prosecution power. Here I draw on my recent article about the Crime Victims' Rights Movement, which explains that in American history the power to prosecute long resided not in the Executive but in private hands. My article observes that, at the time the Constitution was drafted, the dominant mode of state criminal prosecution was private prosecution—that is, prosecution by (for example) victims of crime. When crafting the federal Constitution, the Framers left state criminal proceedings essentially unregulated, meaning that state prosecutions were often initiated by victims rather than government actors.
But in the federal system, it is unclear what the Framer's intended for the prosecution power. So far as can be determined, the Framers never discussed prosecution in connection with federal executive power at the Convention. (See Cassell, supra, at 405). Moreover, most state constitutions at the time of the Framing did not mention, let alone classify, the prosecutorial function. As Professor Stephanie A.J. Dangel has reported, when the Constitution was drafted, five state constitutions included the office of attorney general, but under the judicial articles.
Ultimately, the Framers produced the Constitution with its Appointments Clause, which allows Congress to vest appointment of "inferior Officers" in (among other places) "the Courts of Law":
[The President] … shall appoint Ambassadors, other public Ministers and Consuls, Judges of the supreme Court, and all other Officers of the United States, whose Appointments are not herein otherwise provided for, and which shall be established by Law: but the Congress may by Law vest the Appointment of such inferior Officers, as they think proper, in the President alone, in the Courts of Law, or in the Heads of Departments.
U.S Const., Art. II, Section 2 (emphasis added). In his post, Calabresi asserts that interim U.S. Attorneys are "inferior Officers." And given their limited remit (holding the Office of U.S. Attorney only temporarily) that seems plausible. So I won't explore the issue here. For further discussion, the interested reader should check out Calabresi's (and Gary Lawson's) strong article on the unconstitutionality of Robert Mueller's special counsel appointment, along with Josh Blackman's and Seth Tillman's extensive analysis of related topics.
Treating interim U.S. Attorneys as inferior officers, Calabresi maintains that it "strains credulity" to read the Appointments Clause as allowing Congress to set procedures for "cross-branch appointments." But nothing in the Appointments Clause's text supports that constricted reading. To the contrary, the phrase broadly allows Congress to vest the power "in the President alone" or, alternatively, "in the Courts of Law"—with the choice being made as Congress may "think proper." And Congress is allowed to make its own, proper choice about where to vest the appointment power for "such" inferior officers—that is, officers who include Executive Branch officers.
Moreover, as the Supreme Court explained in Morrison v. Olson, at the Constitutional Convention, "there was little or no debate on the question whether the Clause empowers Congress to provide for interbranch appointments, and there is nothing to suggest that the Framers intended to prevent Congress from having that power." Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 675 (1988). The seven Justices in the the Morrison majority all agreed with this view; the sole dissent, from Justice Scalia, did not challenge it.
Turning next to the office of the U.S. Attorney, in the Judiciary Act of 1789, Congress established a criminal justice system for the small minority of criminal cases handled by the federal system. The Act assigned to the President the power to appoint the Attorney General. In addition, the Act also established a system of federal district attorneys for each of the thirteen judicial districts, with duties including prosecuting in these districts all federal crimes. But while the federal government adopted a public system of prosecution far earlier than many of the state and local governments, nonetheless private citizens continued to be involved even in the federal process.
Professor Dangel explains that, despite the absence of private prosecution in the federal system, private participation continued to some degree. In the early Federal period, private citizens could apparently directly initiate federal prosecutions on their own. Indeed, in a 1794 letter, Attorney General Bradford expressed the view that
[I]f the party injured is advised or believes that the federal courts are competent to sustain the prosecution, I conceive he ought not to be concluded by my opinion or that of the district attorney. If he desires it, he ought to have access to the grand jury with his witnesses; and if the grand jury will take it upon themselves to present the offense in that court, it will be the duty of the district attorney to reduce the presentment into form, and the point in controversy will thus be put in a train for judicial determination.
In addition, Congress bolstered enforcement of federal criminal statutes with private qui tam actions. Courts effectively treated qui tam actions as criminal proceedings.
To be sure, as a matter of practice, federal criminal prosecutions quickly became synonymous with public prosecutions. But the functional reason a right of private prosecution failed to develop in the federal system stems from the happenstance of the limited kinds of federal crimes at the time. As Professor Dangel has cogently explained, "the Supreme Court refused to recognize federal common law crimes which might have given rise to private prosecution." Moreover, "federal criminal statutes during this period dealt with crimes against the Federal Government qua Federal Government, and thus, public officials prosecuted these public crimes." Thus, Calabresi's initial starting premise—that prosecution is an "exclusively executive power"—rests on shakier foundations than is commonly recognized.
The Judiciary Act of 1789 authorized the President to make the appointment of what we now call U.S. Attorneys, subject to advice and consent by the Senate. But could that appointment power, to some degree, be vested in the Judiciary? This particular cross-branch appointment issue has not been litigated before the Supreme Court. But, in other contexts, the Court has examined cross-branch appointments—generally approving them. In Ex parte Siebold (1879), the Court concluded that Congress could vest in the circuit courts the appointment of supervisors of elections. Siebold noted that an earlier case, In re Hennen (1839), had stated that the issue before it (involving a court clerk) could be traced back to an appointment, which was "intended to be exercised by the department of the government to which the officer to be appointed most appropriately belonged." Calabresi cites this statement from Hennen. But Hennen did not provide any analysis of the constitutional issues involved. And, as Siebold later explained, Hennen's observation "was not intended to define the constitutional power of Congress in this regard, but rather to express the law or rule by which it should be governed." 100 U.S. at 398.
Seibold also noted that a flat constitutional rule barring cross-department appointments could lead to endless wrangling over which department was the appropriate one. It was "no doubt usual and proper to vest the appointment of inferior officers in that department of the government, executive or judicial, or in that particular executive department to which the duties of such officers appertain. But there is no absolute requirement to this effect in the Constitution; and, if there were, it would be difficult in many cases to determine to which department an office properly belonged." Id. at 397.
Calabresi acknowledges that Siebold "demoted" Hennen's dicta to a mere statutory observation, while expressing his personal view that "the Supreme Court should re-elevate Hennen to be the lead case on this question." But Calabresi's view implicitly concedes both that Siebold is controlling law today—and that it has been the law in this country for more than 140 years.
Calabresi further concedes that, consistent with Siebold, various forms of authorization for judicial appointment of Interim U.S. Attorneys have existed since the Civil War. See, e.g., Act of March 3, 1863, ch. 93, § 2, 12 Stat. 7687(1863). In 1966, that judicial appointment authority was recodified in 28 U.S.C. § 546:
The district court for a district in which the office of United States attorney is vacant may appoint a United States attorney to serve until the vacancy is filled.
Interestingly, one of the most prominent examples of the exercise of this power was in Utah—and indirectly involved my school (the University of Utah College of Law). In 1974, a vacancy existed for the U.S. Attorney's Office for the District of Utah. The presiding district court judge for the District of Utah (Judge Willis Ritter) had previously been a professor at the University of Utah College of Law. And using his recognized statutory power, Judge Ritter appointed another professor from Utah's College of Law—my former colleague Bill Lockhart—to act as interim U.S. Attorney. (Sadly, Lockhart passed away in 2024.) Lockhart served in the interim position for six months. There, he was responsible for administering President Ford's Clemency Program for Viet Nam draft evaders in Utah. Lockhart granted amnesty to all Utah evaders, supported by a careful memorandum to the Justice Department emphasizing the severe inconsistencies, vagueness and prejudicial delay inherent in prior prosecution policies in those cases.
Judge Ritter's tenure in Utah was marked with controversy. (The tale is well told by Patricia Cowley and Parker Nielson in Thunder Over Zion: The Life and Times of Child Judge Willis W. Ritter (2006).) And Ritter's controversial appointment of Lockhart appears to have served (at least in part) of the basis for Congress to amend the statute governing judicial appointments of interim U.S. Attorneys.
In 1986, in response to a request by the Attorney General that its office be vested with authority to appoint interim United States Attorneys, Congress enacted (former) 28 U.S.C. § 546(d). Under this statute, the Attorney General was authorized to appoint an interim United States Attorney for 120 days and, if the Senate did not confirm a new United States Attorney during that time, the district court was then authorized to appoint an interim United States Attorney to serve until a permanent replacement was confirmed. As a House Report later described things, "By retaining a role for the district court in the selection of an interim United States Attorney, former section 546(d) allowed the Judicial Branch to act as a check on Executive power. In practice, if a vacancy was expected, the Attorney General would typically solicit the opinion of the chief judge of the relevant district regarding possible temporary appointments." See House Rep. 110-58.
It appears that the Reagan Administration did not contest the constitutionality of § 546(d)'s judicial appointment provision. Perhaps the reason is that, if the Administration had litigated the issue directly, it would have lost. In Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654 (1988), the Court disagreed with the view "that there is an inherent incongruity about a court having the power to appoint prosecutorial officers." Id. at 676 "Indeed," the Court held, "in light of judicial experience with prosecutors in criminal cases, it could be said that courts are especially well qualified to appoint prosecutors." Id. at 676 n.13. The Supreme Court recounted that "courts may appoint private attorneys to act as prosecutor for judicial contempt judgments"; that courts may appoint United States commissioners with prosecutorial powers; that courts may appoint federal marshals, who are executive officers; that courts may appoint interim United States Attorneys who, inter alia, prosecute criminal cases; and that "Congress itself has vested the power to make these interim appointments in the district courts." See Morrison, 487 U.S. at 676–77 (citing 28 U.S.C. § 546(d)).
Calabresi seems to acknowledge that Morrison specifically validated § 546(d). But he argues that Morrison is "no longer good law as to … its Appointments Clause holding," because the holding was not followed in either Edmond v. United States, 520 U.S. 651 (1997) or Free Enterprise Fund v. PCAOB, 561 U.S. 477 (2010)." But neither of those two cases provides real support for Calabresi's position.
In Edmond, the Supreme Court rejected an Appointments Clause challenge to the Secretary of Transportation appointing Coast Guard judges, concluding that a statute authorized the appointment and that the judges were "inferior Officers" within the meaning of the Appointments Clause. The Court specifically cited Morrison as part of its analysis. Apart from the "inferior Officer" issue, the petitioners in the case did not raise any other Appointments Clause issues—and, accordingly, the Court did not address Congress's authority.
And in Free Enterprise Fund v. PCAOB (2010), the Supreme Court considered whether the Take Care Clause of the Constitution permitted a principal officer to be given "multilevel protection from removal" by the President. Here again, the Appointments Clause was not the main issue—the President's removal power of an already-appointed official was. And while the Court struck down the problematic removal constraints, the Court rejected an Appointments Clause challenge to the SEC's collective appointment of board members. To be sure, the fact pattern presented in the case involved an appointment by the SEC—not courts of law. But the Court even noted that the "Appointments Clause necessarily contemplates collective appointments by the 'Courts of Law,'" Art. II, § 2, cl. 2, without casting any doubt on the practice.
Finally, Calabresi cites two recent Supreme Court decisions that, in his view, render § 546(d) unconstitutional. The first is Seila Law, 591 U.S. 197 (2020), a decision involving a for-cause restriction on the President's power to remove the director of the Consumer Financial Protection Bureau (CFPB). But this a curious citation for an Appointments Clause argument, as the majority does not cite (much less discuss) Congress's power to vest appointment power in courts. Calabresi argues that § 546(d) is "unconstitutional under Seila Law because it allows the exercise of executive power by someone who has not been hired by the President or his Heads of Departments." But Seila Law analyzes the President's removal power over the director of a purportedly independent Executive Branch agency. Thus, it sheds little light on issues surrounding what appointment power that might be extended to the judiciary. Indeed, at several points Seila Law cites Morrison—a decision clearly supporting § 546(d)'s constitutionality. And one key fact in Seila Law was that the CFPB's structure was "almost wholly precedented"—in contrast to judicial appointment power for interim U.S. Attorneys dating back to the Civil War.
The second case Calabresi cites—Trump v. Wilcox (May 22, 2025)—is just a recent "shadow docket" order only four paragraphs long, granting a stay of a D.C. district court order enjoining the President from removing members of two agencies (the NLRB and MSPB). The focus of the Court's short order was (as in Seila Law) a restraint on the President's removal power. Here again, this authority seems of limited relevance, particularly given Supreme Court's more direct statement in Morrison approving Congress placing appointment power in the judiciary.
While the cases that Calabresi cites say little about judicial appointment of prosecutors, the Supreme Court has decided several cases on this issue, decisions allowing judicial appointments. The Morrison case is a clear example, but others exist as well. In the context of contempt proceedings, the Supreme Court has explained that "it is long settled that courts possess inherent authority to initiate contempt proceedings for disobedience to their orders, authority which necessarily encompasses the ability to appoint a private attorney to prosecute the contempt." Young v. U.S. ex rel. Vuitton et Fils S.A., 481 U.S. 787, 793 (1987) (emphasis added); see also, e.g., United States v. Donziger, 38 F.4th at 304 (upholding judicial appointment of a special prosecutor). The courts also have appointed private attorneys to defend criminal judgments, even when the Justice Department has declined to do so. For example, in United States v. Dickerson (2000), Chief Justice Rehnquist appointed me to defend the Fourth Circuit's decision limiting the scope of Miranda, even though the Justice Department prosecutors were arguing the contrary position for the Executive Branch.
So, to sum up, for Calabresi's argument that § 546(d)'s judicial appointment provision is unconstitutional to work, the Supreme Court would have to:
- read an atextual limit against cross-branch appointments into Article II, section 2, overruling a 140-year-old precedent (Seibold);
- overrule Morrison v. Olson, which directly and favorably cited section 546(d); and
- overrule Young v. U.S. ex rel. Vuitton et Fils S.A., which allowed judicial appointment of special prosecutors.
To me, overturning all these precedents seems unlikely (not to mention potentially unwise). Under existing law, § 546(d) is clearly constitutional.
But let's assume for a moment that Calabresi is correct that § 546(d) is, in fact, unconstitutional. Then what happens? Immediately a severability question would arise, as 546(d)'s judicial appointment sub-section is adjacent, of course, to the earlier sub-sections 546(a), (b), and (c). Subsections 546(a) through (c) authorize the Attorney General to make interim appointments. If the Supreme Court were to strike down § 546(d), it would likely also have to strike down the statute's other related provisions as not severable from each other—potentially depriving the Attorney General of any authority to make interim U.S. Attorney appointments.
To understand the severability issue, it is necessary to lay out the statute's history a bit more. Interestingly, in 2006, the position that Calabresi argues for—complete Justice Department control over interim U.S. Attorneys for an unlimited period of time—was adopted in the PATRIOT Act. See USA PATRIOT Improvement and Reauthorization Act of 2005, Pub. L. No. 109-177, tit. V, Sec. 502, 120 Stat. 246 (2006). But shortly thereafter, controversy arose about how certain U.S. Attorney's had been removed from their offices. And, the next year (2007), Congress responded by enacting legislation—sometimes identified as the "Preserving U.S. Attorney Independence Act"—which went back to pre-existing law. The legislation restored the 120-day limit and judicial appointment provision that remain in the law today.
This congressional action interweaving the various provisions means that, if the Court were to strike down § 546(d), it would likely need to also strike down the statute's other subsections. After finding a part of a statute unconstitutional, under standard severability analysis, the Court "cannot rewrite a statute and give it an effect altogether different from that sought by the measure viewed as a whole." Murphy v. Nat'l Collegiate Athletic Ass'n, 584 U.S. 453, 481 (2018). Thus, a ruling invalidating the interim judicial appointment provision would seemingly necessitate invalidating the Attorney General's appointment power as well. This result does not appear to achieve the goal of broader Executive power that Calabresi seems to be seeking.
Starting from Calabresi's premise that these restrictions on Executive power are undesirable, a stronger argument is not to question the statute's constitutionality but rather to argue (as Calabresi ultimately does) that the Attorney General remains free to make successive appointments for multiple 120-day terms. In a separate post tomorrow, I plan to turn to these issues surrounding how the statute's judicial appointment provision. The statute, while constitutional, might nonetheless be essentially ineffective.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
A really detailed and interesting analysis. When I read Calabresi's post; my initial takeaway was that he was an unprincipled whore. After reading this OP, I think I might have been unfair. I think that Calabresi merely is incompetent as a legal scholar. A legal hack, yes; but not a whore.
I still feel bad for his students . . . but for an entirely different reason.
Calabresi's article was such a weird take: This has to be unconstitutional, because the Supreme Court (allegedly) said recently that only the President can appoint officers, and even though the Constitution expressly says that Congress can delegate the power to name officers to the courts, that can't be what it meant to say, because we know from the Supreme Court that only the President can appoint officers.
It's basically saying that the plain wording of the Constitution is overridden by reading between the lines of shadow docket rulings. It's flat-out bonkers.
The President has the authority has the authority to dictate who prosecutes on behalf of the Federal govt.
Exactly this.
The appointment by judges may be constitutional but the President can just immediately remove her.
Not sure that follows. However, giving task assignments, if any, is presidential.
Why doesn't it "follow"?
Classic VC comment thread. A lengthy, carefully reasoned post only to be immediately dismissed by some yokel who doesn’t know his head from his ass. Bravo.
exactly so long as the president retains the ability to remove the Court's appointee, I think the statue passes constitutional muster.
"I think the statue passes constitutional muster."
"[The President] … shall appoint Ambassadors, other public Ministers and Consuls, Judges of the supreme Court, and all other Officers of the United States, whose Appointments are not herein otherwise provided for, and which shall be established by Law: but the Congress may by Law vest the Appointment of such inferior Officers, as they think proper, in the President alone, in the Courts of Law, or in the Heads of Departments."
I can't even, at a certain point. The actual text of the Constitution states ...
"the Congress may by law vest the Appointment of such inferior Officers, as they think proper ... in the Courts of Law[.]"
How can a statute (a law) that vest the appointment of an inferior officer in the "Court of Law" be ... unconstitutional when it expressly provided for ... in the Constitution?
The Constitution expressly says several items. For example "The right to bear arms shall not be infringed" or "Make no law...abridging the freedom of speech"
Yet, we have several laws that do just that. One can't own a nuclear weapon. And the freedom of speech is abridged in several respects.
One can easily imagine that certain....irregularities...with the phrase "the Congress may by law vest the Appointment of such inferior Officers, as they think proper ... in the Courts of Law" might be "corrected".
It's clearly not necessarily true that every law that regulates or punishes keeping or bearing arms or any kind of speech infringes on "the right of the people to keep and bear Arms" or abridges "the freedom of speech" and "press." No such right or freedom ever was intended to encompass undermining our Constitution.
"We the People" did "ordain and establish this Constitution" to "form a more perfect Union" to more perfectly "establish Justice, insure domestic Tranquility, provide for the common defence, promote the general Welfare, and secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves."
For the foregoing purposes, our Constitution expressly and repeatedly required or precluded or regulated copious speech. Most obviously directly related to the rights and freedoms secured by the First Amendment, Article VI required all state and federal legislators "and all executive and judicial Officers" to expressly acknowledge ("by Oath or Affirmation") that they are "bound" to "support this Constitution;" at the same time, Article VI emphatically precluded any "religious Test" (oath) as "a Qualification to any Office or public Trust under the United States."
"No person" can "be deprived" by any federal official "of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law," so all federal employees (including all judges or attorneys employed by any federal court and all attorneys who are officers of any federal court) must comply with federal law (including federal rules of procedure and evidence) governing speech in legal proceedings. Nobody (including the judge, any party, any attorney, any witness or any observer) has any freedom of speech to obstruct or interfere with due process of law.
"In all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to" a "public trial" in which "an impartial jury" must deliberate and state its judgment.
"In all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right" to
"be informed of the nature and cause of the accusation; to be confronted with the witnesses against him; to have compulsory process for obtaining witnesses in his favor, and to have the Assistance of Counsel for his defence."
"No person," however, can "be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself."
"No person," moreover, can "be held to answer for a capital, or otherwise infamous crime, unless on a presentment or indictment of a Grand Jury, except in cases arising in the land or naval forces, or in the Militia, when in actual service in time of War or public danger."
Regarding keeping and bearing arms, Article I expressly emphasized the power of Congress to enact legislation:
To raise and support Armies . . . ;
To provide and maintain a Navy;
To make Rules for the Government and Regulation of the land and naval Forces;
To provide for calling forth the Militia to execute the Laws of the Union, suppress Insurrections and repel Invasions;
To provide for organizing, arming, and disciplining, the Militia, and for governing such Part of them as may be employed in the Service of the United States, reserving to the States respectively, the Appointment of the Officers, and the Authority of training the Militia according to the discipline prescribed by Congress.
Article I further emphasized the power of Congress to "make all Laws" that are "necessary and proper for carrying into Execution" absolutely "all" the "Powers vested by this Constitution in" Congress or "the Government of the United States, or in any Department or Officer thereof."
Because if the statue did not allow for the removal of that Court appointed inferior by president or inoculated that inferior officer from removal by the president, then there might be an issue with that statue.
*shrug*
As someone who does not believe in the strong unitary executive theory (some thing that is ahistorical), I personally believe that the actual text of the Constitution controls over the penumbras and emanations of an authoritarian make-believe idea of how government should work. In other words, I don't agree with that. I think that it's as stupid as saying that there is a "unitary legislature" so that allowing the Vice President (part of the Executive) to have anything to do with the Senate is wrong, even though it's part of the Constitution. The text, as always, controls over stupid theories.
But with this Supreme Court's recent opinions, maybe?
You're right, so you might find my comment below useful.
I'm confident that "dictate" is not the right word. The first, foremost and constant duty of the President is to "preserve, protect and defend the Constitution of the United States" to "the best of" the President's "Ability." Fulfilling such duty clearly necessarily includes "tak[ing] Care that the Laws be faithfully executed."
Whatever anyone has said or might say about any so-called "core" power of the President necessarily pales in comparison with the core powers of Congress and even more so the powers of the People.
It is important to recall what John Locke said about legislative power in his Second Treatise on Government. The "legislative is" the "supreme power of the commonwealth." "The Legislative Power is that which" can "direct how the Force of the Commonwealth shall be imploy'd for preserving the Community and the Members of it."
Our Constitution requires scrupulous observance of a crucial distinction between Locke's England (and today's UK) and the US. In England and Britain, Parliament was and is the legislative (the supreme) power. In America, the supreme legislative power is divided between the People and Congress. That's why Article VI emphasizes that "the supreme Law of the Land" consists, first and foremost, of "this Constitution," and only after that come "the Laws of the United States which" have been "made in Pursuance" of our Constitution (and all American "Judges" are "bound thereby").
In the U.S., the supreme legislative power belongs to the People, which is why "We the People" were able to "ordain and establish this Constitution" to "establish Justice" and "secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves." As Article I emphasized, the People "vested" in our representatives in "Congress" only part of our "legislative Powers." We vested in Congress the power to "make all" (and only) "Laws" that are "necessary and proper for carrying into Execution" absolutely "all" the "Powers vested by this Constitution" not only in Congress but throughout any part of "the Government of the United States, or in any Department or Officer thereof" (including, obviously, the president, all executive branch officers, and all judges).
In the Report of 1800 by James Madison and the Virginia Assembly (regarding how Congress's Sedition Act of 1798 violated our Constitution), Madison illustrated and emphasized how the legislative powers of Congress are subordinate to the legislative powers of the People,
"The authority of constitutions over governments, and of the sovereignty of the people over constitutions, are truths which are at all times necessary to be kept in mind; and at no time perhaps more necessary than at the present."
In America, "[t]he people, not the government, possess the absolute sovereignty. The legislature, no less than the executive, is under limitations of power. . . . Hence in the United States, the great and essential rights of the people are secured against legislative, as well as against executive ambition. They are secured [ ] by constitutions paramount to laws. This security of the freedom of [speech and] the press, requires that it should be exempt, not only from previous restraint by the executive, as in Great Britain; but from legislative restraint also; and this exemption, to be effectual, must be an exemption, not only from the previous inspection of licensers, but from the subsequent penalty of laws."
So, according to the plain text, structure and purpose of our Constitution, there is no such thing as a "core" presidential power that is not subject to the legislative power of the People (our Constitution) or the legislative power of Congress. That also is why SCOTUS's so-called judgment exempting presidents from criminal statutes enacted by Congress (and prior presidents) to protect the people from criminal usurpations of power was absurdly frivolous.
I think all USAs, permanent or interim, are principal officers—which of course creates even more problems for the statute. But that would solve the problem of whether the courts could appoint them—they couldn’t.
Under the assumption that USAs (permanent or interim) are principal officers, the fix for temporarily filling USA vacancies is that the post can only be filled by someone who 1) is a member of the executive branch, 2) has been confirmed by the Senate, and 3) the position that that person holds has, by law, been imbued with the ability to temporarily assume the role of USA if need be. For instance, the Secretary of Commerce can’t be an interim USA because, while confirmed by the Senate, the office doesn’t have the built-in ability to step in as a USA (I assume; maybe it does, but just go with my hypo for now). Conversely, the USA’s administrative assistant couldn’t be the interim USA because, even if his job duties included the ability to fill in, it’s not a Senate-confirmed position. This method conforms to the Appointments Clause; ensures Senate oversight, and thus democratic accountability; and respects the separation of powers.
I see a difficulty, not in the conclusion, but the path to it. Specifically, including the length of tenure in the determination.
Morrison cited tenure and narrow jurisdiction as factors for consideration, but as Edmond later clarified the Court was not there enunciating a test:
and the military judges in Edmond were found to be inferior officers despite satisfying neither of Morrison's tests for limited jurisdiction or tenure.
Instead Edmond taught that the proper test to apply is
I think US Attorneys are inferior officers under this test. Although the AG can't fire them at will, they do work under her direction (28 USC §519), she can take over any case or assign it to another DoJ officer (§518(b)) and can make recusal rules which if willfully violated result in removal from office (§528).
Some readers may disagree that this level of supervision is enough to make the USA an inferior officer, and that is fair enough. What should be clear though is that there is no daylight between the regular USA and an interim USA in this determination because there is no difference in their supervision. If one is a principal officer then they both are.
Perhaps, what's more useful if just thinking about the Constitutionality of such a provision, is what happens if it was taken to absurd levels.
Let us imagine the following. Congress objects to the current president...yet, can't impeach him due to lack of a 2/3rds supermajority. Moreover, Congress itself cannot appoint inferior officers. So, they use a work around. Congress does the following.
1. Congress passes a law that allows the district court of Alaska to appoint inferior officers to any and all executive branches (assume it slips past a veto). The district court Judge there is a friend of Congress.
2. Congress refuses to confirm "any" of the Presidents nominees for any principle office
3. The "inferior" officers appointed by this district court judge are now "acting" principle officers (since none of the POTUS's nominees have been confirmed).
4. Congress uses these provisions to ignore the President, and run the executive branch with its own nominees.
Would all that be "Constitutional?"
Couldn’t the president just fire the interim appointees as soon as they take office? A sort-of “If that’s the game Congress wants to play, so be it” retaliation?
And if they choose not to be fired? What does the President do?
What does "if they choose not to be fired" mean? I can tell my boss I "choose not to be fired" too, but that doesn't mean I still have my job.
Many things. For example, they argue (in a lawsuit) only their direct superior can fire them, not the POTUS. And their direct superior isn't Senate Confirmed, so...
This would be like claiming "The CEO cannot fire me. My direct superior is a district manager".
If the President can fire your direct superior --- he can fire you as well.
Taking that to court, after the judge stops laughing, would be a waste of time.
Maybe while the President is distracted cheating at golf?
The Constitution isn't bulletproof. Instead of asking whether there is an absurd (your word) hypothetical where hundreds of politicians work in concert to subvert it, you should consider how much more realistic it is that a corrupt unitary executive could amass enough power to do it single-handedly.
"Instead of asking whether there is an absurd (your word) hypothetical..."
Because the precise point of asking such hypotheticals, is to see if there is any outer bounds on when such a provision may or may not be Constitutional.
We have the right to bear arms...but not a nuke. Why not? Again, it's useful to start from the outer bounds.
It's a dumb idea to insist on a Constitution that is proof against every hypothetical.
That applies to any broad framework, really.
Leave it to a bunch of lawyers to argue about a system which is already broken and think that it can all be fixed by arguing about the legality of the broken system.
What am I rambling on about?
The administration of justice in this country and especially at the DOJ. It is highly politicized. The AG is expected to enforce laws independently, but is structurally aligned with the President’s political agenda. As a result, the AG may act in ways that appear politically motivated, undermining trust in impartial justice.
This extends to most of the states as well with elected AGs and state prosecutors.
The United States is the only country in the world that elects its prosecutors. While this practice may seem benign and democratic, it is anything but, with disastrous consequences for justice. That’s because elections affect how prosecutors behave, and not for the better. Prosecutors are meant to balance the public’s interest in prosecuting criminals with the public’s other interest in fairness. Yet when running for reelection, prosecutors become overly pugnacious, sacrificing fairness—which does not play well at the polls—for convictions, which do play well.
It is time to depoliticize the entire administration of justice, locally, in each state and federally. That includes presidential appointments for the USAG.
One proposal is to amend the U.S. Constitution to mirror the TN Constitution which incorporates judicial appointment of the AG. A slight variation of the TN model for the entire DOJ:
The judges of the Supreme Court shall nominate, and by and with the advice and consent of the Senate, shall appoint the Attorney General for the United States. The Attorney General shall hold their office during one term of ten years.
The Attorney General shall nominate, and by and with the advice and consent of the Senate, shall appoint Attorneys for the United States for any district for which a Judge having criminal jurisdiction shall have been provided by law. They shall hold their offices for a term of eight years, eligible to succeed in office for one additional term of office.
The Attorney General and all appointed Attorneys of the United States shall be removed from office on impeachment for, and conviction of, treason, bribery, other high crimes and misdemeanors, or other behavior that renders them unfit for office.
The system is not broken. If anything, there needs to be more democratic accountability, not less. The contemporary problem with the federal judiciary has been there lifetime appointment has allowed some of them to go rogue. (Not an argument by me for changing terms for federal judges, just an observation.) I don't want this same thing to happen to a federal attorney general acting as an independent prosecutor going after political opponents. Ken Starr or Robert Mueller (AKA Andrew Weissmann)
The ultimate remedy here remains impeachment.
Non-political retirement, in other words not pulling an RBG, does much more to incentivize judges retiring than something like term-limits (not something you suggested) which can be gamed by different actors in the system.
However, you do not address the more pressing commentary as regards this article: that of appointments to the DOJ, federal prosecutors and by default state AGs and state prosecutors.
As an example, one study (Okafor, C. O. (2021, October 18). Prosecutor Politics: The Impact of Election Cycles on Criminal Sentencing in the Era of Rising Incarceration (Working Paper No. arXiv:2110.09169). arXiv.) determined the electoral “tough on crime” mantra emphasizes “wins,” even if the “wins” lead to over-punishment or injustice. For example, the disciplinary commission report that sanctioned Michael Nifong—the district attorney who prosecuted Duke University lacrosse players on false rape charges in 2005—noted his upcoming primary as a motivating factor for his misconduct. The pressure to produce wins has led to a “win-at-all-costs” mentality in some offices, because voters reward such behavior.
Moreover, elections provide structural incentives for district attorneys to bring more cases to trial and seek longer sentences for prisoners, which in turn feed the crisis of mass incarceration. A prosecutor is nearly 10 percent more likely to take a case to trial, rather than seek a plea bargain, in the year before he or she runs for reelection, according to a recent study.(Bandyopadhyay, S. & McCannon, B.C. Public Choice (2014) 161: 141. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-013-0144-0). If the prosecutor is running in a contested election, the odds increase another 15 percent. Elections tip the balance too far in the direction of incarceration.
Appreciate this thorough explanation, and its implicit rebuttal of Calabresi's previous post--which had the feeling he was leaving out or ignoring important details harmful to his position.
Because at the heart of it, because the Constitution explicitly allows for the appointment of inferior officers by Congress in "the Courts of Law", this is not facially unconstitutional (unless USA's are not inferior officers). Of course, the unspoken subtext here is the hypothetical were Congress to vest primary/exclusive appointment of all US attorney's in the Courts of Law, would that violate any unitary executive theory/separation of powers? Given that the primary system is not structurally rigged against the president normally appointing his own people, I don't think it is. It's like Professor Calabresi is trying to argue that the exception is the rule, and therefore unconstitutional.
I'm going to pick a tiny but funny nit in what is overall a fine essay. You wrote about Utah Judge Witter, "(The tale is well told by Patricia Cowley and Parker Nielson in Thunder Over Zion: The Life and Times of Child Judge Willis W. Ritter (2006).)" [Bold and underlining omitted because Reason forces that.] The actual title of the Cowley and Nielson book refers to Judge Ritter as Chief Judge, not Child Judge. You might want to fix that.
I know from experience that judges get called many names, but child? That's new.
Was just about to point out this same typo. I had to admit I was pretty intrigued by the thought of child judge--was it because of his youth when he became a judge? A childish temperament? Or was he perhaps focused on juvenile and/or family law, thus serving as a judge over children?
Whatever supporters of any president (including any group of judges, including SCOTUS justices) say about any so-called "core" power of the president necessarily pales in comparison with the core powers of Congress and even more so the powers of the People.
It is important to recall what John Locke said about legislative power in his Second Treatise on Government (because it profoundly influenced the Founders and the Framers and the text and structure of our Constitution). The "legislative is" the "supreme power of the commonwealth." "The Legislative Power is that which" can "direct how the Force of the Commonwealth shall be imploy'd for preserving the Community and the Members of it."
Our Constitution expressly requires scrupulous observance of a crucial distinction between Locke's England (and Britain in 1787-1789) and the US. In England and Britain, Parliament was the legislative (the supreme) power. In the U.S., the supreme legislative power is located, first, in the People, and only second in Congress. That's why, for example, Article VI emphasizes that "the supreme Law of the Land" consists, first and foremost, of "this Constitution," and only after that come "the Laws of the United States which" have been "made in Pursuance" of our Constitution (and all American "Judges" are "bound thereby").
The fact that the supreme legislative power belongs to the People also is why "We the People" were able to "ordain and establish this Constitution" to "establish Justice" and "secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves." It also is why (in Article I), the People emphasized that "All" (and only) the "legislative Powers herein granted" (by the People) "shall be vested in a Congress."
The People "vested" in our representatives in "Congress" only part of our "legislative Powers." We vested in Congress the power to "make all" (and only) "Laws" that are "necessary and proper for carrying into Execution" absolutely "all" the "Powers vested by this Constitution" not only in Congress but throughout any part of "the Government of the United States, or in any Department or Officer thereof" (including, obviously, the president, all executive branch officers, and all judges).
Next, Article II (and the President's oath of office) prominently emphasized that the first, foremost and constant duty of the President always is (merely) to "preserve, protect and defend the Constitution of the United States" to "the best of" the President's "Ability." Fulfilling such duty clearly necessarily includes "tak[ing] Care that the Laws be faithfully executed." Clearly, every power of the president is subordinate, first, to the legislative power of the People (our Constitution) and, second, to the legislative power of our representatives in Congress.
In the Report of 1800 by James Madison and the Virginia Assembly (regarding how Congress's Sedition Act of 1798 violated our Constitution), Madison illustrated and emphasized how the legislative powers of Congress are subordinate to the legislative powers of the People, and the executive powers of the president (and the powers of all judges) are subordinate to both the foregoing legislative powers.
"The authority of constitutions over governments, and of the sovereignty of the people over constitutions, are truths which are at all times necessary to be kept in mind; and at no time perhaps more necessary than at the present."
In America, "[t]he people, not the government, possess the absolute sovereignty. The legislature, no less than the executive, is under limitations of power. . . . Hence in the United States, the great and essential rights of the people are secured against legislative, as well as against executive ambition. They are secured not [only] by laws paramount to prerogative [but also] by constitutions paramount to laws. This security of the freedom of [speech and] the press, requires that it should be exempt, not only from previous restraint by the executive, as in Great Britain; but from legislative restraint also; and this exemption, to be effectual, must be an exemption, not only from the previous inspection of licensers, but from the subsequent penalty of laws."
So, according to the plain text, structure and purpose of our Constitution, there is no such thing as a "core" presidential power that is not subject to the legislative power of the People (our Constitution) or the legislative power of Congress. That also is why SCOTUS's so-called judgment exempting presidents from criminal statutes enacted by Congress (and prior presidents) to protect the people from criminal usurpations of power was absurdly frivolous.