The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Dean Treanor and Georgetown's First Amendment rights
Dean Treanor is right to assert Georgetown's First Amendment right to "teach DEI" in the face of Trump Administration threats.
I'm almost two weeks late to this party, but I wanted to congratulate Dean William Treanor of Georgetown Law for his strong response to the letter sent by Interim U.S. Attorney Ed Martin insisting that Georgetown Law "eliminate[] all DEI from [the] school and its curriculum", and threatening not to hire any Georgetown graduate if it fails to do so.
Dean Treanor writes:
The First Amendment . . . guarantees that the government cannot direct what Georgetown and its faculty teach and how to teach it. The Supreme Court has continually affirmed that among the freedoms central to a university's First Amendment rights are its abilities to determine, on academic grounds, who may teach, what to teach, and how to teach it.
This is a bedrock principle of constitutional law—recognized not only by the courts, but by the administration in which you serve. The Department of Education confirmed last week that it cannot restrict First Amendment rights and that it is statutorily prohibited from 'exercising control over the content of school curricula.' . . .
Given the First Amendment's protection of a university's freedom to determine its own curriculum and how to deliver it, the constitutional violation behind th[e Administration's] threat is clear, as is the attack on the University's mission as a Jesuit and Catholic institution.
I like Georgetown Law (I taught there as a Visiting Assistant Professor from 2006 to 2008, before Treanor's tenure as dean), and though I haven't been a big fan of Georgetown Law's recent approach to free speech, I hope other schools resist the Administration's demands similarly forcefully. (Ed and I were co-clerks at the Institute for Justice in Summer 2001, but I'm on Dean Treanor's side here.)
Mainly, though (because this involves "DEI" and "First Amendment" in close proximity to each other), this is a good excuse for me to plug my own (slightly related) article, just published in Florida Law Review—Expressive Discrimination: Universities' First Amendment Right to Affirmative Action. I've blogged about this before (Parts 1, 2, 3, and 4), but I'll reprint the Introduction below.
Introduction
June is always a big month for Supreme Court watchers, but the last two days of June 2023 were more interesting than usual for constitutional and civil rights law. In one case, the Court made race-conscious affirmative action—which had long been only grudgingly accepted—even more difficult. But the decision in another case paves the way for an argument that private universities have a First Amendment right to engage in affirmative action.
On June 29, 2023, the Supreme Court decided Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. President & Fellows of Harvard College, cutting back on the legality of race-conscious affirmative action in universities and all but overruling Grutter v. Bollinger. This was both a statutory and a constitutional opinion: all universities that accept federal funds are governed by Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964; public universities are also governed by the Equal Protection Clause. But the two have been interpreted to impose identical standards, so the distinction didn't make much practical difference.
The very next day, the Court decided 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis. Lorie Smith, a website designer, decided to enter the wedding-website business; she didn't want to create websites promoting gay weddings or otherwise contradicting her beliefs, but that could have opened her up to prosecution under the Colorado Anti-Discrimination Act. The Supreme Court held that the statute couldn't be applied to force her to create websites she disagreed with. A website is just words and images—"pure speech." If the state made Smith create a website for a gay marriage—just because she was willing to create one for a straight marriage—that would be compelled speech, which would violate her First Amendment rights.
These two lines of doctrine don't usually talk to each other, but they should—especially now.
Suppose you're a private-university president who wants to have affirmative action for faculty hiring or student admissions (or both). You've tried to fit your program within the confines of Grutter. You've steered clear of impermissible interests such as racial balancing or remedying societal discrimination, avoided illegal methods such as quotas or inappropriately numerical targets, and stuck to approved interests such as the value of diversity. Then, on June 29, your general counsel said such efforts should be curtailed or abandoned. After sleeping on it—you sleep late the next morning, so you don't wake up until after the Supreme Court has released its opinions—is there anything you can do on June 30?
Yes, there is.
Lorie Smith's websites were pure speech. But so is virtually all your university's activity. Everything significant that universities do—lectures, homework, exam-taking, paper-writing—boils down to talking and writing. That includes the all-important transcript and diploma, which are just the university speaking to certify what the student has accomplished. If this isn't pure speech, what is?
You think back to an older case: Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, where the Supreme Court upheld the Boy Scouts' exclusion of a gay assistant scoutmaster even though this violated an antidiscrimination statute. The Boy Scouts engaged in expression, part of which included a position against homosexuality. Given this position, forcing the organization to accept a gay person in a leadership position "would, at the very least, force [it] to send a message, both to the youth members and the world, that [it] accepts homosexual conduct as a legitimate form of behavior."
Boy Scouts built on a previous case—the unanimously decided Hurley v. Irish-American Gay, Lesbian & Bisexual Group of Boston, which upheld the right of parade organizers to exclude an LGBT Irish-American organization from the parade even though this violated an antidiscrimination statute. The state courts interpreted this as an exclusion of LGBT people, but the Court recognized that this was an attempt to alter the parade organizers' message. Organizations have the right to choose their message, and sometimes the speaker's identity is the message. This is why you can limit yourself to actors of color for Hamilton or cisgender female contestants for a beauty pageant.
Freedom of speech implies a right against compelled speech: the right to speak includes the right to choose what to say, i.e., the right not to say certain things. The First Amendment also includes a right of expressive association: people have the right to group together to express their views. In the expressive-association context: the right to speak in groups includes the right to choose whom to speak with, i.e., the right to choose whom not to associate with in speaking. We can call this principle—the marriage of the expressive-association right with the right against compelled speech—the principle of "expressive discrimination."
What does this mean for your university's affirmative action programs? Your university is a speaking organization whose "message" may include teachings about diversity. The university speaks not only through its administration but also through its entire scholarly community, which includes faculty and students (perhaps also some staff). Using an antidiscrimination law such as Title VI or 42 U.S.C. § 1981 to force the university to speak through people not of its choosing—which could mean a faculty and student body that don't match the university's notions of diversity—could impede the university's ability to speak. The university's expressive-association right can include the ability to take race into account to create a university community with the desired amount or type of diversity.
Previously, one could have argued that the Boy Scouts expressive-discrimination principle was limited to noncommercial, volunteer organizations such as parades and the Boy Scouts and that it wouldn't protect the discrimination in contracting required for affirmative action for faculty and students. But this is where 303 Creative helps: the Court reaffirmed the right against compelled speech in an economic, for-profit context. Lorie Smith "offers her speech for pay and does so through . . . a company in which she is 'the sole member-owner.' But none of that makes a difference."
The legal landscape on June 30 is thus more promising than it was on June 29. You can assert an expressive-association right to choose your faculty and students because those are the speakers in your pure-speech organization. And this right can trump mere statutory antidiscrimination policies.
And just in time! The day before yesterday, you could simply rely on your affirmative action program's legality. You've never before needed a constitutional theory that would let you ignore the statutes, but now you do. The expressive-association theory can give you what you need and more: if this works, not only can you go back to running your previous programs, but now you can run any affirmative action program you like, even one that would have been illegal under Grutter. If you like, you can use quotas and pursue outright racial balancing or try to remedy societal discrimination, rather than be limited to the single rationale of the educational benefits of diversity. If the government can't force the Boy Scouts to have a gay assistant scoutmaster or force Lorie Smith to design a pro-gay-marriage website, what right does it have to tell your university what speakers to choose?
If only Harvard's lawyers had argued this First Amendment theory. This should be the next frontier in private-university affirmative-action litigation—or the basis of a private university's defense next time it gets sued.
* * *
Part II of this Article presents this theory and explores some of its complexities.
The Supreme Court has never endorsed a strong form of expressive-association rights, whereby restrictions on an expressive organization's ability to choose its members is a per se burden. Antidiscrimination cases such as Bob Jones University v. United States and Roberts v. United States Jaycees are still good law. Your expressive-association claim will thus look better if your facts look a lot like those in Boy Scouts. But then you have a problem. The assistant scoutmaster was an authority figure who spoke on behalf of the organization and was expected to inculcate the organization's values. Many universities aren't like that—at least not with respect to faculty and students—because they have strong faculty- and student-based academic-freedom and free-speech norms.
The universities that are the best fit for an expressive-association theory are those that expect or require faculty and students to promote university values, which might require weakening academic-freedom and free-speech norms. Other universities might be able to use the theory, but it won't be as good a fit, so the result will be harder to predict.
Part III addresses various follow-on questions:
- Does the racial angle matter, given that the other cases arose in the context of sexual-orientation discrimination? (The cases don't support treating these different types of discrimination differently.)
- Does the market angle matter, since the other cases arose in the context of volunteer or nonprofit activity? (303 Creative suggests it doesn't.)
- What about laws such as Title VI, which don't regulate universities outright but merely impose conditions on recipients of federal money—bringing into play the looser constraints of the unconstitutional conditions doctrine? (This is the greatest hurdle. But the unconstitutional conditions doctrine bars pulling funding from the entire university based on discrimination by any single unit.)
- Could public institutions use this theory too? (No.)
Part IV asks how far this theory can go. Based on recent litigation, I identify three flexibilities in the doctrine, which help us understand what doctrinal movement is plausible.
- One is what it takes to make a substantial burden on an association's expression.
- Another is what governmental interests can be characterized as "compelling," so as to overcome the expressive-association right under strict scrutiny.
- But the biggest question is what activities are characterized as "expressive." That's a threshold issue—if the action isn't expressive, then First Amendment analysis isn't even relevant. You can't unilaterally make nonexpressive conduct, such as tax avoidance, expressive by talking about it or claiming civil disobedience. This threshold question preserves the core of antidiscrimination law in the vast majority of cases, even for expressive associations. But some activities, such as flag burning or parades, are inherently expressive. The test has to do with social expectations and how the particular conduct is likely to be perceived. This test is flexible, and different attitudes on the part of courts can lead to different results.
* * *
The key takeaway, though, is that—at least in private education, and possibly more broadly—the First Amendment expressive-association theory is potentially liberating for affirmative action. The expressive-association cases have been criticized as giving a free pass to racists, sexists, and homophobes. (Perhaps; but they have rights too.) But affirmative action can dwarf all of that. For decades, affirmative action has tried to fit into the constraining framework of Equal Protection/Title VI—satisfying neither affirmative-action opponents who advocate colorblindness nor proponents who would prefer programs forthrightly grounded in reparations for past injustices or remedying current inequalities. Now that Equal Protection/Title VI doctrine has come down strongly for colorblindness, the First Amendment theory has the potential (at least in some private universities) to convert affirmative action from a grudgingly allowed concession to a strongly protected right.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Congratulations to Dean Treanor on an excellent response. I suppose adding at the very end, "Pound sand." would have been gilding the lily.
You can indoctrinate people in your cult as a private entity. You just don't have a right to taxpayer funding for it.
Yes you do. DEI is not a religious doctrine. If the federal governement wants to give out funds to colleges, it cannot say that certain viewpoints cannot be taught because merely because it designates those viewpoints as “cults.”
While I disagree with a number of things more zealous advocates of DEI have done, the fact of the matter is this country has had some setious problems in its history, and talking about those problems and their consequences for people today openly is part of what a university is supposed to do.
Can you say "badges of slavery"?
Talking about history isn't DEI.
HTH,
MP
This situation had literally nothing to do with "taxpayer funding" for Georgetown.
The receipt of Federal funds doesn't mean "taxpayer funding"?
This situation had nothing to do with the receipt of federal funds by Georgetown.
Sure.
And Georgetown doesn't have to receive any Federal funding, including student loans.
Whatever....
If the Justice Department wants to know what Georgetown Law teaches, it could ask for a course catalog. Do they still do paper catalogs, or is it all on-line these days?
It could but it would be more effective to send someone along to listen to the classes. Or pay students to record them.
As I recall, no one said they couldn't teach DEI.
They just said federal tax dollars would not go where DEI is taught.
And, oh by the way, most of the voters agree.
Recall better. Martin's threat had nothing to do with where federal tax dollars would go. Not surprisingly, since the USAO does not play any role in deciding that.
Today on NPR, senior NPR correspondent David Folkenflik read a letter sent to him from the DOJ in late February telling him he was being suspended from his other job as foreign correspondent for Voice of America. The letter tells him he is being investigated for social media posts he made that were not sufficiently in accord with president Trump's policies.
You hear that , hayseeds? It's really happening. The Red Hats are coming for teachers, journalists, judges...you name it. If he wasn't a Russian asset, I'd swear he's in thrall of Mao
"coming for teachers, journalists, judges."
You don't have to sell me on Trump you know.
Just a little cultural purge like the old days
Its your side that had the cultural revolution.
Yeah, Bob. We know how you think, fascist asshole.
And nobody tell me I'm exaggerating calling Bob a fascist. He is openly supporting "coming for teachers, journalists, judges" who disagree with The Leader.
Maybe you'll get a sense of humor one day.
Its an internet meme, from one of the Spiderman movies. It mocks the original "point".
You weren't joking.
You ain't exaggerating. And all these angry children are just getting started
He's also a Pinochet fan, don't forget.
Who isn't? He revolutionized the Helicopter Tour industry.
hobie thinks the concept of cancel culture and Presidents removing people from the other political party from positions that the President is in charge of was invented in 2025 lol.
Then just fire the man, if that's all it is. Why a DOJ investigation? I don't think this journalist committed national crimes like Trump did.
Good to see Sasha still advocating for racism, at least there is one honest Marxist Democrat out there.
Good ol' Marxist Democrat Sasha Volokh.
He's also been known to recite poetry....
DEI teaches that people should be treated differently based on race. People who believe that certainly shouldn't be prosecutors. Prosecutors should believe in equal justice under law.
I have no more issue with a U.S. Attorney not hiring law students who are taught to treat defendants differently based on their race than a hospital administrator not hiring medical students who are taught the magical healing power of crystals, even if the dean of the medical school has a First Amendment right to teach it.
"DEI" does not teach anything.
LIVY: Experience is the teacher of fools.
DAVID THE PEDANT: Experience doesn't teach anything.
FD WOLF: So we should ban experience because I don't like learnin' stuff.
An uitterly juvenille and thoughtless piece, that "Cake Baking is not speech" and you revive some of that dead bigotry yet again
Did you even read the SCOTUS rebuke where virtually all the Colorado judges said that Jack's Christianity was disgusting and it was the cake that spoke for him
Do the very judges who agreed with your outcome did not agree at all that cake is not speech!! Everybody says dumb shit but you keep repeating it
In view of these factors, the record here demonstrates that the Commission’s consideration of Phillips’ case was neither tolerant nor respectful of his religious beliefs. TheCommission gave “every appearance,” id., at 545, of adjudicating his religious objection based on a negative normative “evaluation of the particular justification” for his objection and the religious grounds for
it, id., at 537, but government has no role in expressing or even suggesting whether the religious ground for Phillips’ conscience-based objection is legitimate or illegitimate. The inference here is thus that Phillips’ religious objection was not considered with the neutrality required by the Free Exercise Clause. The State’s interest could have been weighed against Phillips’ sincere religious objections in a way consistent with the requisite religious neutrality that must be strictly observed. But the official expressions of hostility to religion in some of the commissioners’ comments were inconsistent with that requirement, and the Commission’s disparate consideration of Phillips’ case compared to the cases of the other bakers suggests the same.
Bob Jones v. US has a fairly obvious application to the Georgetown situation. In Bob Jones the court applied strict scrutiny (under the free exercise clause rather than the free speech clause). It found that the government's interest in eradicating racial discrimination was compelling, and denying the tax exempt status was the least restrictive means. Today racism is called "DEI", but it's still racism. The government still has a compelling interest in eradicating it. And means such as denying funding and not hiring graduates seem comparable, if anything less extreme, than denying tax exempt status. So if we believe that Bob Jones v. US was rightly decided (and this is certainly open to question), then it seems to follow that the Trump administration is justified, even under a strict scrutiny standard, in going after Georgetown as it is.
DEI as practiced at Georgetown (not DEI as an amorphous slander) equating to racism is something the government must prove. Even if they overcome that substantial hurdle, the government must show that eradicating advocation for DEI is a compelling interest. Note, that is different than Bob Jones which was engaging in racist conduct.
If you could point us to a race blind sex blind sexual orientation blind gender blind DEI initiative that would help your argument.
What does that have to do with what Georgetown teaches?
It has to do with whatever Josh means by DEI. He objects to “DEI as amorphous slander” but postulates the existence of something called “DEI as practised at Georgetown” which is other than racist / sexist etc, by definition.
I’d like an example, as it sounds a bit like “dry water” to me. Feel free to offer your own answer.
Right; the IRS in Bob Jones did not attempt to dictate curriculum to the university. The case was about its admissions policies — conduct — not its speech. (Note: I think that the decision was wrong as a matter of statutory interpretation, but that's irrelevant to the larger point.)
(Too, the policy being challenged did not impose any penalties on students merely because they had attended the school.)
> Right; the IRS in Bob Jones did not attempt to dictate curriculum to the university. The case was about its admissions policies — conduct — not its speech. (Note: I think that the decision was wrong as a matter of statutory interpretation, but that's irrelevant to the larger point.)
Do you honestly believe that Georgetown Law isn't engaging in racial discrimination in its admissions and hiring decisions under the label of DEI? If they aren't, then I agree Bob Jones v. US is less applicable. But I don't think either of us really believes that they aren't.
> (Too, the policy being challenged did not impose any penalties on students merely because they had attended the school.)
Do you think that the people making hiring decisions for the government wouldn't have passed over a Bob Jones graduate for an otherwise identical graduate of a university that didn't discriminate? It may be that nobody wrote that down as an explicit policy, but I'd be quite surprised if it wasn't the standard practice between Bob Jones v. US and when Bob Jones University ended its discriminatory practices.
I don't know, but (a) if it were, why would that be a reason to penalize its graduates? and (b) if Martin had limited his threats to those related to admissions/hiring, that might be relevant, but he expressly attacked the curriculum.
> (a) if it were, why would that be a reason to penalize its graduates?
I can think of three reasons:
(1) You might be considering hiring Georgetown Law grads, at least in part, because you think the Georgetown Law admissions office is a really good filter. If the Georgetown Law admissions office is discriminating on race, then that signal is stronger for applicants of some races and weaker for applicants of other races. It becomes less useful purely in terms of finding the best applicants. It also becomes impossible to use that signal without indirectly engaging in racial discrimination yourself.
(2) If Georgetown Law does do a lot of racial discrimination, and a student chose to attend Georgetown Law, then either the student failed to notice the discrimination, or didn't care much about it. Neither possibility speaks well of the student.
(3) You might think that eradicating discrimination is important, that Georgetown Law cares about the employment prospects of its graduates, and that therefor by rejecting its graduates you apply pressure on the institution to stop discriminating.
Any combination of these three seems like a perfectly good reason to me.
> b) if Martin had limited his threats to those related to admissions/hiring, that might be relevant, but he expressly attacked the curriculum.
If this ends up in court, I would bet the government's arguments will not be limited to the curriculum. If Georgetown were to stop discriminating in admissions and hiring, but continue to teach DEI in its curriculum, and the government didn't back down, then yea, I think Georgetown would probably have a good Free Speech claim there. But we both know Georgetown isn't going to do that. They are either going to get rid of all of the DEI, or fight for all of it.
"The key takeaway, though, is that—at least in private education, and possibly more broadly—the First Amendment expressive-association theory is potentially liberating for affirmative action. The expressive-association cases have been criticized as giving a free pass to racists, sexists, and homophobes. (Perhaps; but they have rights too.) But affirmative action can dwarf all of that. For decades, affirmative action has tried to fit into the constraining framework of Equal Protection/Title VI—satisfying neither affirmative-action opponents who advocate colorblindness nor proponents who would prefer programs forthrightly grounded in reparations for past injustices or remedying current inequalities. Now that Equal Protection/Title VI doctrine has come down strongly for colorblindness, the First Amendment theory has the potential (at least in some private universities) to convert affirmative action from a grudgingly allowed concession to a strongly protected right."
I just threw up a bit reading that. "segregation now, segregation tomorrow, and segregation forever" was pithier, though.
I don't want to liberate affirmative action. I want to kill it off, to the maximum extent possible within the legitimate reach of government, and if the legitimate reach of government is going to be curtailed to preserve it, it should be curtailed equally for all similar discriminatory ideologies.
I'll say this again: Jim Crow demonstrates that you can persuade a working majority or politically dominant minority that discrimination against others is good.
The end of Jim Crow, and the public's rejection of racial discrimination, including 'affirmative action', demonstrates that you can persuade a working majority that discrimination against others is bad.
It has never been demonstrated that you can persuade a working majority of the population that discrimination against themselves is good.
The advocates of 'affirmative action', 'reparations', and all other excuses for modern racial discrimination, risk a partial victory: Convincing the majority that discrimination isn't a moral wrong, without convincing them that it should be against themselves.
Fortunately I don't think the risk is that high. Sasha Volokh is an advocate for a morally degenerate cause that is, happily, losing.
You will do whatever authoritarian bullshit it takes to get you what you want.
Thats why you're the worst libertarian.
I note how many ideological paeons are in this post. And I recall CS Lewis's quote about the authoritarianism of idealists being the most destructive.
She is literally trying to find ways to preserve and extend racial discrimination. I don't need to pretend I don't find that disgusting; I have opposed racial discrimination all my life, and I have no tolerance for people who think it's ok so long as the victims are the right color.
Sasha's a dude (who by the way has never written anything in favor of affirmative action).
Fair enough on the dude point; I was under the impression Sasha was a girl's name, my bad.
The above sure sounds like somebody who likes affirmative action...
Arguing that there's a First Amendment right to do something that people want to do is not the same as being in favor of that thing. Otherwise, you might think I'm in favor of Nazis marching...
Rutan v. Republican Party of Illinois, 497 U.S. 62 (1990), was in substance an expressive association case regarding government employment. Justice Brennan there wrote for the Court:
497 U.S. at 77-78. I fail to see how the same First Amendment principle that applies to a prospective employee's political party affiliation would not apply as well to his choice of educational institution. “To the victor belong only those spoils that may be constitutionally obtained.” Id., at 64.
This whole thing is sordid cancel culture payback, of the "reputational damage to your organization, wink wink" type.
Me: Nobody should be doing this.
Others: Depends on who's doing it.
"Oh no! They're doing to us what we've been doing to them. I am shocked! Shocked!"
Ironically, one could add the precursor sentence, "Your winnings, sir." Which is what politics is all about.
Krayt, you repeat that theme endlessly. I think you are mistaken to do it.
Your theme seems to me to depend tacitly on a notion that both sides you posit rely alike on institutional constraints for government—or at least that both sides disregard them equally. I do not think that is even close to accurate.
I think the Ds put considerable reliance on institutional constraints for government, and make violation of those a principal basis for their critiques of MAGA/Trump. No doubt the Ds are less rigorous during self-critiques, but it ought to be evident to you that the Ds do somewhat constrain themselves according to the standards they apply to others.
By contrast, MAGA/Trump has distinguished itself by explicit intent to negative institutional constraints. They have made blanket opposition to institutional constraints a test of MAGA/Trump inclusion. They even omit to criticize the Ds for their own violations of institutional constraints, preferring instead to launch tu quoque style attacks, which tend more to validate institution bashing than to support institutional reliance.
In short, MAGA/Trump hates institutional reliance so much, it disdains to use the best weapon available against its opponents. MAGA/Trump advocatres understand that to use that weapon would open their own ranks to more powerful blows than they could inflict on their opponents.
I hope you can discern how that contrast undermines your repeated theme. If you cannot discern that, your own advocacy begins to look actually nihilistic.
The right is responding to the fact that the left has captured most of the relevant institutions, mostly because they were actively trying to, and the right largely couldn't be bothered to resist until it was too late.
As a result, 'institutional constraints' = continued Democratic control". Now, maybe this is defensible for genuinely private institutions, but it isn't for governmental institutions, which need to be responsive to the voters. Those latter need to be brought back to SMALL 'd' democratic control.