The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The Collective-Action Constitution: A Brief History of an Idea
Second in a series of guest-blogging posts.

Something like the idea animating The Collective-Action Constitution—or a narrower, more implicit, and more intuitive version of it—has been around for a long time and has been articulated in many places. At the Philadelphia Convention and state ratifying conventions, and in public essays and private correspondence, Madison, Hamilton, Wilson, Washington, and other prominent nationalists emphasized both the need for federal power in cases of general interests, separate state incompetence, or regulatory disuniformity and the need to stop states from creating interstate problems. The Constitution was drafted and ratified primarily to achieve these goals, not to limit federal power or to protect state authority or individual liberty.
John Marshall was at the Virginia ratifying convention, and collective-action reasoning supports—and may have informed—canonical federalism decisions of the Marshall Court. The most important example is McCulloch v. Maryland (1819), which embodies the book's argument. The Court upheld federal power to create a national bank as convenient to carrying into execution federal powers that solve collective-action problems for the states, and prohibited states from causing collective-action problems by taxing the bank. Another example is Gibbons v. Ogden (1824), which upheld federal power to regulate navigation under the Interstate Commerce Clause, thereby preventing states from causing collective-action problems by granting monopoly power over navigation routes.
Over the nineteenth century, federal courts helped entrench a political and economic union by policing state protectionism. Collective-action reasoning supported and likely influenced their invalidation of state laws under the dormant commerce doctrine, which today limits the extent to which states can cause collective-action problems by being protectionist or burdening interstate commerce.
In the early twentieth century, the federal government made—and the Supreme Court rejected—collective-action arguments in important federalism cases. One example is Hammer v. Dagenhart (1918), which invalidated a federal ban on the shipment in interstate commerce of goods produced by child labor. The Court there blessed a regulatory race to the bottom. A distinguishing feature of the Court's federalism jurisprudence from the late 1800s to the 1930s was its frequent rejection of the idea that multistate collective-action problems partially justify federal power.
Informal expressions of the collective-action concept ramped up during the New Deal and Great Society. Robert Stern, a lawyer for the federal government who overcame anti-Semitism to build a great life in the law, authored a stunning law review article that presaged modern theorizing about the relationship between the Interstate Commerce Clause and the regulation of multistate collective-action problems. Certain Supreme Court briefs filed by the federal government during the Great Depression reflected Stern's research and thinking. (See pages 7-8 of The Collective-Action Constitution for citations.) Perhaps relatedly, collective-action rationales seemed to inform transformative federalism decisions of the Court during the constitutional crisis of the New Deal, just after the "switch in time that saved nine" in 1937: NLRB v. Jones & Laughlin Steel Corporation, Steward Machine Company v. Davis, and Helvering v. Davis.
During the post-New Deal era that reoriented constitutional law, the Court invoked collective-action logics in justifying Congress's power to regulate interstate commerce. One example is United States v. Darby (1941), which overruled Hammer v. Dagenhart in upholding federal minimum-wage and maximum-hours regulations of manufacturers of goods shipped in interstate commerce. Another example is Wickard v. Filburn (1942), which validated Congress's attempt to raise the price of wheat on the interstate market by upholding a federal wheat-production quota as applied to a farmer who exceeded his quota but used the excess wheat for home consumption and livestock feeding. The Court also implicitly used collective-action thinking in continuing to invalidate state laws under the dormant commerce doctrine in such cases as H.P. Hood & Sons, Inc. v. Du Mond (1949).
Similarly, collective-action reasoning supports the Court's decisions upholding the Civil Rights Act of 1964 just after it was passed. This is (of course) not because collective-action problems impeded the ability of all states, Southern ones included, to champion racial equality and facilitate the interstate mobility of African Americans. Rather, the Court's decisions in Heart of Atlanta Motel, Inc. v. United States (1964) and Katzenbach v. McClung (1964) were lawful because Southern racism impeded the ability of most other states to protect interstate travel by African Americans, and the Interstate Commerce Clause lets Congress settle disagreements among states about whether collective action is warranted in the commercial sphere—and to pursue this goal when accomplishing it would benefit the rest of the states more than it would harm majorities of the electorate in Southern states. To act, Congress need not first prove empirically that all states have been trying and failing to pursue the regulatory regime in question; like in Darby and Wickard, it suffices for Congress to rationally conclude that the states face a cost-benefit collective-action problem.
The current era saw an increase in use of the collective-action idea on and off the Court. One example is United States v. Lopez (1995), where the Court likely sensed the absence of a multistate collective-action problem within a reasonable time horizon. For the first time since the 1930s, the Court declared a federal law—a ban on firearms possession in school zones—beyond the Interstate Commerce Clause. Another example is Gonzales v. Raich (2005), where the Court seemed to offer a collective-action rationale in holding that Congress can use its interstate-commerce power to prohibit the local cultivation and use of marijuana in compliance with state law permitting such use. As in Wickard, the Court deemed reasonable the federal government's concern about diversion of the regulated products across state lines—cost externalizations that Congress could reasonably deem to exceed internalized benefits.
Turning to contemporary legal scholarship, collective-action reasoning has explicitly appeared in the writings of an ideological diverse group of constitutional law scholars, judges, and attorneys, most of whom have focused on the Interstate Commerce Clause. Prominent examples include Michael McConnell, Jacques LeBoeuf, Donald Regan, Richard Levy, Robert Bork and Daniel Troy, Maxwell Stearns, Akhil Amar, Stephen Williams, Jack Balkin, Andrew Koppelman, and Stephen Calabresi. Robert Cooter and I expanded the scope of analysis from the Interstate Commerce Clause to Article I, Section 8. (For citations, see pages 10-11 of the book.)
So, even judging from this incomplete sketch of the role of collective-action reasoning in American constitutional thought over the past two-plus centuries, it seems fair to describe this idea as important, enduring, and, at times, influential.
It is revealing that collective-action thinking has a history; if it were entirely novel, it could not provide the basis for a persuasive structural theory of the Constitution. To date, however, the idea has not been examined rigorously and comprehensively. As noted, past discussions have been relatively casual, implicit, or intuitive. Or they have lumped collective-action problems together with other concepts such as interstate externalities, without distinguishing among different kinds of collective-action problems or specifying the analytical relationship between them and spillover effects. Or else they have focused on specific constitutional provisions, especially the Interstate Commerce Clause.
The Collective-Action Constitution leverages conventional legal and historical materials, as well as concepts and insights from political science and economics, to examine the extent to which collective-action logics illuminate the Constitution as a whole—the document, its Founding history, its underlying structural principles, and its evolving interpretation outside and inside the courts. The book's conclusion is that a collective-action account has significant explanatory power descriptively and normatively, but that it also has limits. Identifying the limits of the theory is as important as identifying its promise, because the limits help define the idea of collective action more sharply and give it greater explanatory power where it does apply. The book shows the great extent—previously underappreciated—to which the Constitution empowers the federal government to solve collective-action problems for the states and prohibits states from thwarting federal solutions to such problems or generating them.
The book also clarifies the contexts in which other rationales are required to justify federal power, especially legislative and judicial protection of most constitutional rights. Rights protection concerns how a state relates to its own inhabitants, which is a different question from how it relates to sister states or the federal government. Accordingly, the Collective-Action Constitution must be supplemented with what the book calls the Reconstruction Constitution to capture the functions of the Constitution more fully in modern America. Even regarding rights protection, however, the book argues that collective-action reasoning plays a role.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
I have some pushback when it comes to Civil War amendments (which you skipped) and the Civil Rights era. I would argue those are less collective action issues and more about protecting other values. Of course, the Civil War Amendments purposefully altered the status quo to limit a State's ability to regulate things internally when those things didn't have externalities that needed to be dealt with. Similar to the Civil Rights amendments, it was just a recognition that it was the right thing to do.
That being said, although I'm pushing back, I'm doing it with qualifications. The biggest area of externalities comes from the democratic process itself. By prohibiting citizens from voting, those states allow a smaller group to disproportionately influence national policy by monopolizing those state's representatives. Every state has a mixture of political views and our system is designed so regional votes (even within states) can join with votes from regions of other states to change national policy even if the majority of a particular state disagrees. But, if one state puts the thumb on the scale within their state, it could force other states to do the same. It's the reason the Electoral College reform proposals generally don't go anywhere (and only Nebraska and Maine split votes).
I think it's right that this was the animating purpose of Article I powers (the instruction to the Committee on Detail proves that) and a powerful argument for federal power.
Having said that, I do think text matters, and extending the commerce power to purely local matters potentially offends the text which extends only to commerce among the states (and with Indian tribes and foreign nations). Raich is probably the worst offender here-- the notion that a sick woman growing her own medical marijuana is causing an effect on the interstate market is a totally manufactured argument made by a court that didn't want to call into question or undermine the War on Drugs.
Collective action is a good metric for resolving the close cases, but I think the best interpretation of the Commerce Clause is that if an activity is either non-economic or purely local, it isn't within the federal government's power.
Truly personal use and of something that is illegal federally is a pretty extreme case. But a large enough group of "personal use" growers who start sharing their crops intrastate would affect interstate commerce, by distorting the market for (other, legal) pharmaceuticals serving similar purpose.
Sharing the crops interstate is definitely commerce among the several states, though. You don't need to extend federal power to personal intrastate noncommercial possession to regulate that.
Agree 100% with your comment regarding Raich.
I would add that the decision to stretch the commerce clause to that ridiculous degree in Raich was wrong in and of itself, whether in furtherance of the crappy war on drugs, or any other collective action problem imagined by Congress.
The author takes the view that it is sufficient "for Congress to rationally conclude that the states face a cost-benefit collective-action problem" for Congress to grant itself a power. Text be damned?
The author speaks about limits to this collective action problem solving, so will be interesting to see where he sets them.
How does the phrase "collective action" differ from simple democracy? Early examples of commerce clause items, where it was about stopping states from stepping all over each other isn't a collective action thing. That's a mandate from The People to form a more perfect union, for the general welfare of free and open trade among the states, which is to say, the people of the states.
You then lament a law against the sales of the product of child labor, then praise a law against southern discrimination. Well, who could be in favor of those horrors? But you go into a long diatribe to arguement about how some detailed effect on interstate commerce. Punching the south in the nose over it is a collective action. Your agrument boots on the ground is not. And a democratic action is a better description still, as large numbers, who lost, got punched. That's not some happy large group kumbaya. That's old school politics.
The phrasing to shoehorn "collective action" into this seems strained. It also ignores the larger "collective action" concept where The People informed the federal government what it could not transgress, and, oddly, for a prime, constitutionally-described collective action, militias, and why individuals can keep arms to support that.
But ignore that. It is an example of using "collective action" as justifier for "whatever action this or that person wants to push." That very ruling acknowledged many individual states already had similar laws, collective action at the state level, I suppose. Why isn't that good enough? See again the strained reasoning to punch the South in the nose.
I am fine with the punch, as I have a soft spot for taking freedom by force. But I am seeing less amd less reason to think "collective action" is a noble reason, and just the same old arguments of politicians, scoundrels.
The most endearing qualities of our Constitution were made by Madison who was not a lawyer.
An open mind thinks clearly through problems and is not burdened by needed and excessive education. Even doctors can be narrowed by excessive education which indoctrinates a set path and a closed mind. Far too many people, our society, put too much faith in 'experts'. Looking up for answers, comforts, assurances defeats advancement.
This topic with our Constitution is important, no doubt. What was created in 1787 was radical by far and created far more good than detractors words which never will be. But, our document was still a makeshift thing of compromises.
Solving by collective-action requires adherence to recognizing the underlying collection, that being a collection of States - a Republic. A republic is where differences remain, to some degree, if the people in each so choose to have them. This gives the whole a greater strength just as much as being united, in other areas, does too for other reasons.
To the extent of what constitutes collective-action, the need for resolving nationally verses not, is what is still, and must always be, in question.
Looking to government and law to solve problems may be a failure of individual ability to resolve and personal desires which need to be reexamined too.
"The Constitution was drafted and ratified primarily to achieve these goals, not to limit federal power or to protect state authority or individual liberty."
The Constitution generally was ratified to expand federal power, the Articles of Confederation (which deserves more study than it receives) felt to be too weak.
Nonetheless, the Constitution itself balanced various interests, and some general theme alone should not blind ourselves to that.
I think U.S. v. Lopez was one of the more convincing federalism cases though a jurisdictional hook is still available in most cases. It turns out to be academic in most cases.
Raich is a sympathetic case. If it was available, I think a liberty interest argument would be the best bet. "The Constitution of the War on Drugs" is an excellent new book (free online) that discusses the many aspects of the matter.
But, as a matter of federal commerce power, a pinpoint citation of her situation is wrong-headed. She is part of a wider marijuana market that has interstate and international effects.
The medicinal medicinal market as a policy issue is generally benign. As a commerce matter, is widespread and appropriately regulated under the Commerce Clause.
Raich was not buying or selling, but she nevertheless was engaged in the market -how so?
How did her actions interfere with Congressional plans to extinguish the interstate and international markets? Surely if she grows her own, then she has no need to resort to the interstate or international markets. If Congress forbids her to grow her own, does it not "force" (as the term is used in Wickard) her into the interstate and possibly international market? How is that a reasonable regulation in support of Congress's aim of extinguishing the interstate and international markets?
What Congress is actually doing is trying to eradicate possession and use of marijuana within the home via the commerce clause.
Far from being wrong headed, a pinpoint citation of her situation is enlightening regarding the extent which the commerce power has been abused.
Correction: should have wrote the term "force" as used by judge Silberman, discussing Wickard while upholding PPACA in DC circuit 2011.