The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
A Major New Defense of the Major Questions Doctrine
Legal scholar Ilan Wurman argues the controversial doctrine is justifiable on textualist and linguistic grounds.
The once-obscure major questions doctrine (MQD) has become a major focus of controversy, since the Supreme Court used it in three - yes, major - rulings over the last two years. The three cases are the eviction moratorium decision, the OSHA large-employer vaccine mandate case, and West Virginia v. EPA. MQD may also end up playing a decisive role in the loan forgiveness cases currently before the Court.
The doctrine requires Congress to "speak clearly when authorizing an [executive branch] agency to exercise powers of vast 'economic and political significance.'" Critics had advanced a variety of charges against the major questions doctrine and the Court's use of it, including that it is politically motivated, that the line between "major" and relatively minor questions is arbitrary and unclear, and that the doctrine is incompatible with textualism.
In a forthcoming Virginia Law Review article, prominent constitutional law scholar Ilan Wurman offers an important and in some ways compelling new defense of MQD. Here is the abstract:
In its past term, the Supreme Court formalized what it calls the major questions doctrine. The doctrine, as currently formulated, appears to require a clear and specific statement from Congress if Congress intends to delegate questions of major political or economic significance to agencies. The doctrine has been almost universally assailed on the right by scholars who argue that the doctrine is inconsistent with textualism and on the left by those who claim it is a recently invented, functionalist tool devised to reach anti-administrativist results. One can explain at least some of the cases, however, in a way that constructs a coherent doctrine in which importance has a significant but narrow role in resolving interpretive questions involving ambiguity or uncertainty. Thus understood, such a doctrine could be defensible, if not as a substantive canon, then as a kind of linguistic canon. Unlike other linguistic canons, such a canon would be about how people and lawmakers use language to accomplish results in a circumscribed range of contexts—namely, the delegation of important authorities, whether to other private actors, to government actors in Constitution, or to government actors in the executive department. But unlike substantive canons, it would not relate to a substantive value encoded in the Constitution or in longstanding tradition. Existing empirical work about how legislators legislate, and insights from the philosophy of language, suggest that such a doctrine may be consistent with textualism, and historical research further reveals that a canon of this type may be a longstanding feature of constitutional, contract, and statutory interpretation in related contexts. More provocatively, these same intuitions about importance may explain some substantive canons that are difficult for textualists to justify.
The usual defense of MQD is that it is a tool for enforcing constitutional constraints on the delegation of legislative power to the executive. Wurman argues that it can instead be justified on textual and linguistic grounds.
In the article, he outlines a number of justifications for this conclusion. For example, he cites survey data indicating that most people involved in drafting laws on Capitol Hill support some form of presumption against delegation of major issues to the executive. This evidence is significant for purposivists who advocate interpreting laws in accordance with congressional intent. But it also matters to textualists, as drafters' views provide at least some evidence of the "ordinary meaning" of a statute at the time of enactment.
Most interestingly, Wurman highlights linguistic studies showing that ordinary people expect greater clarity and more evidence to resolve important issues than relatively minor ones. I think that he is on to something here. But it is not, by itself, enough to justify MQD. If people seek greater clarity and evidence on important issues, that may support greater judicial scrutiny of major issues, as opposed to minor ones. But it doesn't necessarily lead to a presumption against delegation of major questions to the executive. It could be people want more evidence and clarity to decide such an issue either for or against delegation.
In an earlier post, I outlined what I think is a stronger textualist justification for MQD, one that actually points in the direction of a presumption against delegation:
In most situations, people expect greater clarity and precision when granting an agent broad power, than when authorizing something narrower. For example, my wife and I recently hired a contractor to repair the old and somewhat dilapidated deck attached to our house. Imagine we signed an agreement giving the contractor the authority to "modernize and improve" the deck, and he then proceeded to tear the whole thing down and replace it with a bigger and more modern structure…
[M]ost ordinary readers of the agreement would readily understand that the contractor had exceeded his authority. Tearing down and replacing the entire deck is a big, expensive step that requires clearer and more specific authorization than a vague mandate to "modernize and improve." By contrast, if the contractor had taken the much more limited step of replacing a few decaying floor boards, most people would agree his actions were properly authorized, even though the agreement doesn't specifically mention such replacement.
The same point applies to statutory language. If anything, most ordinary readers probably assume that vast grants of legal authority over millions of people require even more clarity and precision than do contractual agreements like the deck replacement. For example, in the loan forgiveness case, the Biden Administration relies on a vague provision of the HEROES Act that allows the executive branch to "waive or modify" regulations governing federal student loans to justify cancellation of over $400 billion in student loan debt. Even if semantics "divorced from context" suggests that mass cancellation qualifies as a type of waiver or modification, contextual ordinary meaning indicates that such an enormous delegation of power requires greater precision.
I also think that MQD can potentially be justified by nondelegation considerations, at least so long as the Supreme Court is unwilling to rigorously enforce nondelegation directly.
Wurman's article is a major contribution to the debate over major questions, and there is much more there than the points I have highlighted in this post. Obviously, however, it probably won't be the last word in this important debate.
I should also emphasize that neither Wurman's reasoning nor my own necessarily proves that any specific judicial use of MQD was justified. As I have previously written, I believe the Court got it right in the eviction moratorium and vaccine mandate rulings (though I differ with some of the details of its reasoning in the latter case), and would be justified in using MQD again in student loan forgiveness cases (though I also think the Court could justifiably rule against the Biden Administration even without reference to the doctrine). West Virginia v. EPA strikes me as a tougher case; Justice Elena Kagan's dissent makes a strong argument that the text of that statute is clear enough to satisfy MQD requirements. Obviously, even readers who accept the general idea of MQD might differ with my assessment of one or more of these cases.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
The doctrine requires Congress to “speak clearly when authorizing an [executive branch] agency to exercise powers of vast ‘economic and political significance.'”
The central issue I have with the MQD is that it shifts discretion and responsibility from the elected branches to the unelected judiciary. When Congress grants the executive branch authority in an area, the President is given the power to exercise that authority as he and his administration see fit. The decisionmaking power, particularly with reference to the economic and political scope of the decision, rests with the President. His discretion is then subject to a check from voters and Congress. If the scope of his actions are deemed too broad, voters can push back expressing their disapproval, or Congress can push back by passing legislation that narrows the scope of the authority. Congress is subject to the same influence from voters, who can push their representatives to enact narrowing legislation. In this process, the scope of authority, both political and economical, are matters of discretion that are decided by the elected branches and the voters via the political process.
Under the MQD the Court inserts itself into the process using a legal rule that allows it to substitute its own discretion to determine whether the economic and political scope of the exercise of power is “significant” or not. Whether the scope of the action is significant or not is a political question that cannot be determined by a clear legal standard. I mean, the doctrine literally asks about the “political significance” of the action. The courts should be focused on legality of an action, not on the action’s political significance.
Fantastic comment! One hundred percent correct.
It's a much quicker feedback loop for Congress to confirm it's intent.
Especially now that Congress and the executive are on notice that congressional intent needs to be made clear.
Let's take 2 MQD cases as examples, West Virginia and the still to be decided Student Loan forgiveness.
Why didn't Congress clearly allow the EPA's single source rule in the Inflation Reduction Act, that was actually a Climate Change spending bill.
Why hasn't Biden asked Congress to clearly authorize his student loan forgiveness program since the courts seem to have doubts about it's legality.
I'm guessing the reason is because neither Student Loan forgiveness notthe EPA' regulation in WV were ever congressional intent.
The swiftness of the feedback loop is neither here nor there. For that matter, neither is Congressional intent, unless the text is ambiguous.
Your list of questions are all begging the question, in fact. If the text is ambiguous, then the judiciary should as normal order do their jobs and suss it out. If not, then they say that.
This is a second bite at the apple for the judiciary, with the judiciary itself determining if a second bite is warranted. As QBC noted, that's some really broad discretion to the judiciary above and beyond it's regular statutory interpretation job.
I’ll point out the classic case of the Lilly Ledbetter fair pay act, where the Supreme Court decided the statute of limitations started when a company instituted a discriminatory pay scheme, not when they pay scheme was discovered.
RBG famously lobbied in her dissent for congress to pass legislation to fix the statute which they did.
There are dozens of cases where the Supreme Court has said that if Congress intended the result that the petitioners want its up to Congress to clarify that.
In fact the only circumstances where the MQD prevents any executive regulation is when Congress declines to authorize it. That’s a good thing.
At the top I said the feedback aspect is neither here nor there.
castro -
Kazinski gives a good explanation of the basis for the MQD
"In fact the only circumstances where the MQD prevents any executive regulation is when Congress declines to authorize it."
Its basic separation of powers - If congress did not authorize the action, then the executive branch cant implement the action -
As you continually ignore, they didn't need a new doctrine for this, they already did this regularly based on the wording of the enabling statute. They only needed to invent MQD when the language didn't unambiguously rule out the executive action.
Alpheus W Drinkwater 52 mins ago
Flag Comment Mute User
As you continually ignore, they didn’t need a new doctrine for this, they already did this regularly based on the wording of the enabling statute. They only needed to invent MQD when the language didn’t unambiguously rule out the executive action.
AWD - As you continue to ignore - Congress had to authorize the action - the executive branch cant implement what hasnt been authorized.
MQD is still the courts stating that the executive branch cant do what hasnt been authorized - Why is basic constitutional law so hard for you to grasp
AWD – Your argument against MQD boils down to the false belief that the executive branch should be able to implement actions not authorized by congress as long as congress did not specifically say no.
Finished with you. You simply can't seem to comprehend the point.
Thus do you lithely leap the issue under discussion.
You adhere to the same argument conservatives do when they say the judicial branch has no power to review the laws passed by the legislature.
You just allow it when Congress pushes it off onto the executive branch.
I would argue that’s even worse.
I cordially invite all to join in disallowing vague laws and statements from power hungry weasels from being extended long after the fact by those same power hungry weasels.
Even if we go along with everything you say, all of it applies across the board not to 'major questions.'
This seems a very common issue with those speaking up in favor of the MQD - they argue for a radical departure from current delegation caselaw. Which is not MQD in either magnitude or scope.
Thank god the public has confidence there are no power hungry weasels among the judiciary.
Hardly a sign of being power hungry when the supreme court tells the executive "you don't have that power, Congress does."
A power hungry court would say "You don't have that power, so the court will have to rule by decree."
The Court saying after they make that determination they get to make it again seems to arrogate them some power beyond their usual.
If the executive does t have the power, you don’t need MQD to say that.
"His discretion is then subject to a check from voters and Congress."
Yes, many elections turn on regulations.
Its a completely illusory "check".
So is the "check" by congress, they create these vague laws so as to avoid responsibility.
"Most ordinary readers of the agreement would readily understand that the contractor had exceeded his authority." Most ordinary readers of the agreement would agree that:
1. Wurman did a lousy job of drafting an agreement.
2. Wurman was stuck with the lousy agreement he signed. And,
3. If they ever needed a lawyer, they would not hire Wurman.
If he can't make up a better example than that maybe he should recognize the weakness of his argument.
I was once warned by a lawyer friend that as a layman I can easily be misled into thinking that I can understand legalese because it has the appearance of being written in vernacular English. I take that advice seriously although my reading of the MQD leaves me with several impressions. The first is that much of the problem could be avoided if the legislature wrote better laws. When Congress authorized the EPA with a modest budget and dowdy headquarters in southeast Washington, it did so at a time when carbon aerosols were not considered "pollutants" that would have given this disfavored stepchild of an agency the authority to regulate virtually every human activity, or even humans themselves, as emitters. Even in the common knowledge of the day, Congress should have used precise language on what was to be regulated. The other is that MQD seems to be setting the courts up for a lot of work unless a threshold for what constitutes "major" can be articulated.
MQD seems to be setting the courts up for a lot of work unless a threshold for what constitutes “major” can be articulated.
It also provides a convenient loophole for judges to strike down regulations they don't like but can't really find a problem with.
When the FCC was created in 1934, we didn't have the internet, cell phones, or any of a number of related communications technologies. This sort of thing isn't uncommon. If the overall mission of the agency is general, like "The mission of EPA is to protect human health and the environment," it doesn't seem to matter whether issues before them existed when the agency was created but that they respond to them as they arise. And, as QuantumBoxCat notes, if Congress or the voters feel differently, they have the power to make changes.
Regulators under Shawn's approach:
We'll take the power we want, even if we can't prove to a court it's legally ours. If you don't like it, you can try to take it away. Good luck with that!
Check out an enabling statute sometime.
It looks like this:
-Broad purpose/mission
-Vehicles that may be used to fulfill said purpose (grants, regulations, etc.)
- this is further constrained by the APA.
-Later added on specific programs Congress wants this agency to execute
It's not a plenary grant of power by any means, though it is flexible enough to be adaptable through time within the constraint of means and ends above, absent Congressional amendment (which happens)
None of it really allows the unlimited powah scenario you made up.
Line two assumes the conclusion. I think the old-timers call that begging the question.
Is your argument that agency practice is to go beyond their enabling statute? Because there’s an existing remedy for that, and it has nothing to do with the MQD.
Disclaimer: I work for an Agency, and deal with both OMB/regulatory and legislative constraints as part of my day job. So my perspective is not disinterested.
That's a nicely expressive uppercase "A" on, "Agency."
he cites survey data indicating that most people involved in drafting laws on Capitol Hill support some form of presumption against delegation of major issues to the executive.
Yeah. Surveys of politicians and their staffs is bound to produce accurate results. Besides why don't these people include some sort of language about this in the damn bill, since they are the ones drafting it.
"Yeah, I just told the guy to paint the house without specifying a color, but I really didn't want him to paint it blue." If you don't want him to pick the color, tell him.
In most situations, people expect greater clarity and precision when granting an agent broad power, than when authorizing something narrower.
Not necessarily. You may well simply name goals and delegate broad power if you think the agent is particularly expert and trustworthy, especially if your own knowledge is limited. Perhaps more important, you might do so if dealing with the issues that arise would be complex and time-consuming.
Maybe if Congress is allowed to delegate its authority to agencies (under whatever justification) it should require any rules to be approved and modified by Congress before going into effect.
"should require any rules to be approved and modified by Congress before going into effect"
They should. No real reason not to do so.
I can think of no reason why Congress shouldn't be allowed to write that into the law. (But surprisingly there's a major overlap between people who believe in non-delegation and people who believe in some form of the unitary executive.)
"doctrine is incompatible with textualism"
Duh.
Delegation of legislative functions to the executive is unconstitutional root and branch but the court lacks the courage to strike down the whole doctrine so they limit it by the MQD.
Apparently the framers and ratifiers did not agree with your position, since the ones serving in Congress did a fair amount of delegation, even on major questions. See for instance Mortensen and Bagley's paper "Delegation at the Founding."
The same Congress that passed 14A also segregated DC schools, an early Congress passed the Sedition Act. Congress was not involved with drafting the Constitution in any event.
Is any of that intended to be a defense of your position that delegation is unconstitutional? I was being nice and arguing the point on your home turf of originalism. And members of the first few Congresses were just as involved in drafting the constitution as the first President and Secretary of the Treasury were, and originalists never tire of citing their actions in support of some originalist argument.
Precisely. Rules, policies, regulations, etc. If it has the force of law it is a law. And should be voted on by the legislature.
The doctrine requires Congress to "speak clearly when authorizing an [executive branch] agency to exercise powers of vast 'economic and political significance.'"
Note the untethered presumption in favor of uncritically accepted economic ideology lurking in that one.
I am disappointed that this was not written by Maj. Major Major Major (Ret.)
Where my mind goes when anyone here makes a reference to "Heller."
For example, he cites survey data indicating that most people involved in drafting laws on Capitol Hill support some form of presumption against delegation of major issues to the executive.
That is surprising, given that delegations usually happen when Congress can't or won't decide an issue itself.
Which is why the MQD is so important.
The actions being litigated are major power grabs by the executive because Congress won’t give them the authority they want.
They are aided and abetted by Chevron which has been misread to allow agencies to do almost anything if there is some ambiguity in the legislation.
The MQD is really just a addendum to Chevron where “Major Questions” are not entitled to Chevron deference.
“ Generally, to be accorded Chevron deference, the agency’s interpretation of an ambiguous statute must be permissible, which the court has defined to mean “rational” or “reasonable.” In determining the reasonableness for the particular construction of a statute by the agency, the age of that administrative interpretation as well as the congressional action or inaction in response to that interpretation at issue can be a useful guide; if Congress was aware of the interpretation when it acted or refrained from action, and when the agency’s interpretation is not inconsistent with the clear statutory language.
https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/chevron_deference
Kaz- The objection to the MQD is that prevents the executive branch from implementing policy not authorized by congress. Simple separation of powers - Congress makes law, not the executive branch.
"The actions being litigated are major power grabs by the executive because Congress won’t give them the authority they want."
No. Even if they are major power grabs, they are not clearly outside the language of the enabling legislation. If they were, SCOTUS could so rule without the need for any new doctrine.
If Congress, who made the original delegation, believes the Executive is acting far outside the powers they intended to delegate, they can pass corrective legislation. Their inaction should not give the Judiciary the power to step in. Just the opposite, in fact. It is up to the Legislature to set the limits of the delegation, through the text they enact.
The Judiciary should be guided only by the legislative language. MQD is just an excuse to ignore the language.
AWD 's comment - "The Judiciary should be guided only by the legislative language. MQD is just an excuse to ignore the language.MQD is just an excuse to ignore the language."
AWD - You are correct with your first statement " The Judiciary should be guided only by the legislative language. "
You still get the basic concept wrong with your second statement - The executive should likewise be guided by the legislative language. MQD is only the courts stating that the executive branch cant ignore the language.
Completely incorrect. You need to read up on how MQD works, and when it is applied. You don't seem to understand it at all.