The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
"The Profit Motive: In Defense of Shareholder Value Maximization"
From my UCLA colleague Prof. Stephen Bainbridge.
I asked Prof. Bainbridge whether I could cross-post this from Corporate Finance Lab, and he kindly agreed:
What is the purpose of a corporation? Is it, as Nobel Economics laureate Milton Friedman famously claimed, "to increase its profits"?[1] Or is it, as the Business Roundtable—a group of approximately 200 mostly USA corporate CEOs— claimed in 2019, "generating good jobs, a strong and sustainable economy, innovation, a healthy environment and economic opportunity for all."[2]
In the academic sphere, the weight of scholarly opinion has tilted substantially towards stakeholder capitalism in recent years.[3] The late law professor Lynn Stout dismissed shareholder value maximization as a mere myth, albeit a powerful one she claimed "causes companies to indulge in reckless, sociopathic, and socially irresponsible behaviors."[4] Canadian law professor Joel Bakan went even further by condemning the business corporation itself as a "pathological institution" whose relentless pursuit of profit has psychopathic attributes.[5] In making such arguments, they reflect a widely shared narrative that "corporations are powerful, evil, malevolent, bad-actors intent on profit-making at the expense of the health, safety, and well-being of individuals."[6]
In the investing world, there long have been so-called socially responsible investors, who structured their portfolios using various social justice filters that excluded companies believed to have negative social and environmental impacts. Although it was claimed that socially responsible investing was a profitable strategy, it was primarily justified by moral and ethical arguments.
Today, however, as investor interest in ESG metrics has grown, there has been a distinct shift in recent years from moral and ethical justifications to financial justifications. Although many ESG investors likely are still motivated by traditional socially responsible investor concerns, ESG investing is explicitly premised on the belief that ESG oriented portfolios provide superior risk-adjusted returns to traditional portfolios lacking ESG or social responsibility filters. Hence, for example, the three largest institutional investors—asset managers BlackRock, State Street, and Vanguard—all claim to have embraced ESG because they believe that ESG factors are positively correlated with firm performance. They offer investment funds that supposedly invest exclusively in firms that score highly in ESG measures and that exercise their voting rights as shareholders to support ESG policies. ESG-focused investors thus are supposedly pushing both asset managers and portfolio companies to be more ESG friendly.
In light of these developments, what the present moment requires is a defense of shareholder value maximization that takes those developments into account. Or, to paraphrase William F. Buckley, what the moment needs is for someone to stand athwart the tracks of corporate governance and yell "stop" as the stakeholder capitalism train pulls out of the station.
Which is precisely what my new book, The Profit Motive: In Defense of Shareholder Value Maximization, does.
Three major themes animate the project. First, any conception of corporate purpose that embraces goals other than creating value for shareholders is inconsistent with the mainstream of U.S. corporate law. Second, directors do—and should—have wide and substantially unfettered discretion as to how they go about generating shareholder value. Although many commentators claim that those statements are inconsistent, in fact they both reflect fundamental normative principles deeply embedded in U.S. corporate law. Third, a shareholder-centric conception of corporate purpose is preferable to stakeholder capitalism.
The reader may well ask: Why should we care about corporate purpose?
Put simply, corporate purpose matters because corporations matter. Corporations are "far wealthier and far more able to negatively affect our individual lives than virtually any local government or even most Federal agencies."[7] Worse yet, like elephants crashing through a forest, corporations can trample individuals and communities underfoot without even meaning to do so. Indeed, the corporation has aptly been called "the perfect externalizing machine."[8] By incorporating a business, it becomes possible for the owners of the business—whether intentionally or not—to externalize substantial costs and risks onto corporate constituencies such as employees or creditors and society at large.
The externalities problem has been around since corporations were first vested with limited liability. As corporations grew ever larger in the wake of the industrial revolution, however, the scope of the problem likewise grew. In an industrial economy, limited liability is of particular concern because it may encourage overinvestment in hazardous activities. Because the shareholder can externalize some part of the risks associated with such activities, those activities could have a positive value for the investor even though they have negative net social costs.
Having said that, however, the corporate purpose debate goes beyond simply the negative externalities inevitably resulting from corporate activities. It also asks whether corporations should be managed so as to generate positive externalities. Should managers conduct the corporation's business so as to generate benefits to stakeholders and society in general? Advocates of stakeholder capitalism commonly contend that the profit motive discourages corporate directors and managers to ignore not just the social costs of corporate activities but also the potential for corporate activities to generate social benefits.
In many cases, however, corporate actions that benefit stakeholders—such as employees—help the firm become more profitable and thus redound to the benefit of shareholders. When the corporation faces a true zero-sum decision, however, one must make a choice between the competing interests of stakeholders and shareholders. In such cases, the law requires directors to prefer shareholder interests. The Profit Motive defends that claim as both a descriptive and normative matter.
If executives such as those who signed the Business Roundtable's 2019 statement on corporate purpose really tried to run their companies according to the altruistic principles laid out therein, they would find it an impossible task. Developing the set of objective and quantifiable metrics necessary to operationalize stakeholder capitalism will prove an intractable problem. Even if the requisite set of metrics could be designed, managers cannot reasonably be expected to balance the huge number of competing factors necessary to account for the varied interests of the firm's many constituencies.
Worse yet, stakeholder theory inherently carries with it a serious conflict of interest. While corporate social responsibility empowers honest directors to act in the best interests of all the corporation's constituents, it also empowers dishonest directors to pursue their own self-interest. There is a very real risk that directors and managers given discretion to consider interests other than shareholder wealth maximization will use stakeholder interests as a cloak for actions taken to advance their own selfish interests.
The case for shareholder value maximization is not just a negative one. Pursuit of shareholder value maximization leads to more efficient resource allocation, creates new social wealth, and promotes economic and political liberty. To be sure, there will always be externalities. Just as pursuing profit is baked into the corporation's DNA, so is externalizing costs. There is no such thing as a free lunch. The theory and evidence recounted in The Profit Motive, however, suggests that the balance comes down strongly in favor of shareholder value maximization.
Readers interested in still more information about The Profit Motive may wish to watch my video, in which I discuss the arguments in the book at greater length.
The blog of the author ProfessorBainbridge.com, was named by the ABA Journal as one of the Top 100 Law Blogs of 2007, 2008, 2010, 2011, and 2012.
Stephen M. Bainbridge
William D. Warren Distinguished Professor of Law
UCLA Law
[1] Milton Friedman, The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase Its Profits, N.Y. Times, Sept. 13, 1970, § 6 (Magazine), at 32, 33.
[2] Business Roundtable, Our Commitment (2019), https://opportunity.businessroundtable.org/ourcommitment/.
[3] See Martin Petrin, Beyond Shareholder Value: Exploring Justifications for a Broader Corporate Purpose 4 (Nov. 1, 2020) (explaining that "leading scholars are discussing concepts such as the need for 'purposeful' corporations, and, generally, there seems to be a broad consensus that pure shareholder value thinking has become outdated"), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3722836; Christina Parajon Skinner, Cancelling Capitalism?, 97 Notre Dame L. Rev. 417, 418 (2021) (observing that "scholarly antipathy toward capitalism (and its instantiation in corporate profit-seeking) has become more fervent over the past eighteen months").
[4] Lynn Stout, The Shareholder Value Myth vi (2012).
[5] Joel Bakan, The Corporation: The Pathological Pursuit of Profit and Power (2004).
[6] Linda S. Mullenix, Ending Class Actions as We Know Them: Rethinking the American Class Action, 64 Emory L.J. 399, 407 (2014).
[7] Daniel J.H. Greenwood, Essay: Telling Stories of Shareholder Supremacy, 2009 Mich. St. L. Rev. 1049, 1072 (2009).
[8] Lawrence E. Mitchell, Corporate Irresponsibility: America's Newest Export 53 (2008).
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Pursuit of shareholder value maximization leads to more efficient resource allocation, creates new social wealth, and promotes economic and political liberty.
That's a pretty extreme assertion. Does Bainbridge offer any support, or is it just an article of faith?
You can sort of dimly see the argument for the first part if you ignore externalities, as Bainbridge seems to, but the business about promoting economic and political liberty needs much more than just his opinion.
Sigh. For support you can see the Milton Freidman article quoted at the beginning of the post, or classical economics more generally.
Posts like this are an indictment of our educational system. Any educated person should understand the arguments behind a claim like this, whether you agree with them or not.
While corporate social responsibility empowers honest directors to act in the best interests of all the corporation's constituents, it also empowers dishonest directors to pursue their own self-interest.
Which calls urgently for an analysis to see whether prioritizing profit works any better to suppress director dishonesty, not to mention manager dishonesty.
Also unmentioned? The corruption of national politics—and the potential for personal corruption of directors and managers—inherent in the practice to empower corporate managers to tap corporate funds for political purposes—which laws enabling dark money in politics enable them to do at pleasure, without regard even to the profit interests of shareholders, let alone shareholders' political interests. Shareholders are no more empowered than anyone else to see what their money did after it vanished into the dark money machinery.
Isn't that part of the capitalist flexibility though; the ability for shareholders to assess which companies are more transparent and reliable? Which companies have higher/lower risks?
If I understand Stephen's point, he is saying that managers and directors at public companies often put their own interests ahead of the shareholders', and that's difficult or impossible to stop.
Companies fight like hell to prevent binding shareholder votes on executive compensation, for example. And it's really hard for the shareholders to do much about it.
"Shareholders are no more empowered than anyone else to see what their money did after it vanished into the dark money machinery."
Sounds like a corporate governance issue. If you don't like the amount of visibility you get into how corporations spend their money, invest a more transparent company.
So should corporations' dogged pursuit of profit be constrained by nothing other than out-and-out legal prohibitions? That's a principle that should bother both those on the right who want corporations to be free to exclude abortions from their employer-provided health insurance and those on the left who want them to be free to avoid suppliers who contribute to climate change.
A corporation is a creature of the state, given priveleges that the state believes will result in an overall public benefit. If members of an association wish to do business purely for their own interests and without any regard whatsoever for the welfare of anyone else, why can’t they jolly well do so with full personal liablity for all their members, like any ordinary party?
Corporations used to be individually chartered by legislatures for specific purposes, individually considered, that the legislature thought would benefit the state. Nothing prevents going back to that. As a lesser step, state legislatures could require that corporations consider interests of others besides their shareholders as a condition for recaiving a corporate charter. And Congress could impose such a requirement on corporations doing interstate commerce.
Pursuit of shareholder value maximization leads to more efficient resource allocation,
Looking at this more closely, I think it's dubious as a general proposition. Large corporations do not, usually, operate in what we would consider competitive markets. They tend to seek monopoly power, and they exercise it to some degree.
As soon as that starts to happen you move away from efficient allocation of resources.
Note that we don't have to be talking about pure monopolies here, just companies with some control of their prices.
And again, of course, the existence of negative externalities pretty much introduces inefficiency.
Consider this scenario:
You are CEO of a company that operates a manufacturing plant in a country where environmental laws are non-existent, very weak, or poorly enforced. You plan to make some changes to your production methods in the interests of lowering costs.
The new method produces some nasty waste products which you can dump in the river with no legal consequences. But there are villages downstream that rely on the river for drinking water, and whose diet includes fish that will be poisoned. Dumping the waste will have disastrous effects on the health and wellbeing of the villagers.
An alternative to dumping the waste is to spend money to treat it or otherwise dispose of it safely.
Your choice.
Defining 'stakeholders' as 'shareholders' at least has the advantage of making it easy to know who the 'stakeholders' are.
Once you start picking other stakeholders, how do you pick? There are advocacy groups on both sides of most issues. Picking one or the other is just the board justifying their own preferences.
(My sense is that corporations ought to put their governing principles in their bylaws. I can ask people to become investors in my company by buying shares, but they should know whether I am going to spend their money^h^h^h^h run the business with an eye to making money for them, or doing good for the world, or I suppose doing evil for the world :-). But I don't think I should be able to take their money while promising one thing, then go back on that promise.)
Absarkoa, left out completely? What the per-share-voting corporation does out of sight, to promote political outcomes at least some shareholders do not want. Balance sheets do not disclose purposes for which dark money gets spent. Shareholders cannot reckon or judge what they are not permitted to see.
Also left out? Inability of natural persons who have nothing at all to do with the corporation to compete politically with the corporation's managers. The corporation's managers take money from shareholders. The managers spend it to influence policy outcomes they do not disclose to anyone—except to politicians, who receive largesse, or get denied largesse, in either case to influence policy which applies to everyone.
Rational expectation is that managers who make spending decisions to influence policy will benefit personally by the policy influence the money pays for. Rational expectation whether that policy influence benefits corporate shareholders, or harms them, is guesswork. Expectation whether citizens unaffiliated with the corporation benefit by undisclosed policy influence is . . . not rational.
Whatever its benefits or demerits for shareholders, corporate governance which not only ignores stakeholders more broadly, but which also competes surreptitiously against them politically, cannot be trusted to serve the public interest.
The whole point is that corporations don't exist to serve the public interest. They exist to serve their owners' interest.
I hope the book quotes liberally from Milo Minderbender.
Everyone has a share!
Oh cool, another defense of cigarette companies looking at their own research showing that their products kill people, and then squashing it and pivoting to advertising to kids.
"There is a very real risk that directors and managers given discretion to consider interests other than shareholder wealth maximization will use stakeholder interests as a cloak for actions taken to advance their own selfish interests."
Yes, there is such a risk and the founders of our nation discussed such risk and took steps to avoid it when developing our system of general governance, leaving to us the task of avoiding such risk in other spheres. Who better to know the risk of greed and self-interest than the wantonly greedy and self-interested few who sat to discuss the Constitution‽ The venerable secondary school history text _Conflict and Consensus in Early American History_ brushes the topic by reprinting the 1925 Charles Beard article "An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution" and other documents. Even the (2012?) Zachary Goldfarb article "How We Misread the Numbers That Dominate Our Politics" appearing in the -gasp- The Washington Post offers some insight.
Another thought. This does nothing to respond to one of the major criticisms of the current "maximize shareholder value" philosphy: it's short-sighted.
If the CEO can take an action that'll increase shareholder value in the next few quarters, but absolutely tank the company in the next five years? Then current prevailing corporate governance says the CEO should take the action. That it screws the company (and the shareholders) in the long run is irrelevant.
Sustainable, consistent growth and profit is similarly irrelevant to maximizing returns for the next quarter. Long-term planning? That's for chumps.
That… is not the current prevailing corporate governance.