The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Justice Kavanaugh on Strict Scrutiny
In many areas of constitutional law, the Court allows a constitutional right to be overcome when a restriction passes "strict scrutiny"—i.e. (to oversimplify slightly), when the government can show that restricting the right is the "least restrictive means" of serving a "compelling government interest."
In some fields, such as free speech or race classifications, the inquiry is "strict in theory but [almost] fatal in fact": Very few restrictions pass the test. But in other areas, such as religious exemptions governed by RFRAs or RLUIPA (statutes that borrow the strict scrutiny test from constitutional law), a lot of restrictions must pass—no Justice thinks, for instance, that people should get religious exemptions from laws banning homicide or theft or vandalism or trespass, or for that matter from most tax laws and other important regulatory regimes. At the same time, a lot of others should fail. The details of how strict scrutiny plays out end up being quite important, but while the Court has a lot of precedents applying strict scrutiny, many of the key questions (such as how one can tell whether an interest is "compelling") remain unresolved.
I've long been interested in the subject (see, e.g., my criticisms of strict scrutiny in my 1996 Freedom of Speech, Permissible Tailoring, and Transcending Strict Scrutiny and in Part II of my A Common-Law Model for Religious Exemptions), and I was therefore especially interested in seeing Justice Kavanaugh's concurrence discussing the matter in today's Ramirez v. Collier:
[T]he Court's holding implicates significant issues about how the Court decides whether a State's asserted interest is sufficiently "compelling" and how the Court assesses whether less restrictive means could satisfy that compelling interest. This case illustrates both the difficulty of those inquiries and the important role that history and state practice often play in the analysis.
The compelling interest standard of RLUIPA—like the compelling interest standard that the Court employs when applying strict scrutiny to examine state limitations on certain constitutional rights—necessarily operates as a balancing test. The Court starts with a heavy presumption against a state law that infringes the constitutional or statutory right in question. The Court allows state infringement on that right only when the State has a sufficiently "compelling" interest.
But what does "compelling" mean, and how does the Court determine when the State's interest rises to that level? And how does the Court then determine whether less restrictive means would still satisfy that interest? Good questions, for which there are no great answers. Sometimes, the Court looks to a State's policy-based or commonsense arguments. Often, the Court also examines history and contemporary state practice to inform the inquiries.
{The strict scrutiny test requires the government to demonstrate a "compelling interest" in order to justify imposing a burden on certain constitutional rights. That test was first applied by this Court in certain First Amendment cases in the late 1950s and early 1960s. The test can be difficult to apply because it arguably "permits and even requires judges to engage recurrently in only minimally structured appraisals of the significance of competing values or interests in many cases." In RLUIPA, Congress used the term "compelling" interest without further defining it.}
Here, the State asserts that it has a compelling interest in ensuring the safety, security, and solemnity of the execution room. To further those interests, the State has sought to restrict the number of people in the room, as well as their activities. As the United States pointed out at oral argument, any disruption or interference could be "catastrophic." And a religious advisor would not ordinarily be allowed in a public hospital's operating room during a major life-or-death surgical procedure, so why should one be allowed into the execution room?
The Court has no difficulty reaching the commonsense conclusion that the State has a compelling interest in ensuring safety, security, and solemnity in the execution room. The more difficult question is: How much risk of disruption or interference must the State tolerate in order to accommodate the inmate's religious liberty claim under RLUIPA?
The Court concludes that, even if audible prayer and physical touching are allowed, the State can still sufficiently ensure safety, security, and solemnity in the execution room. The Court suggests that the risk of disruption or interference is conjecture and can be addressed in other ways. For example, security officers in the room could immediately intervene if the religious advisor accidentally or intentionally disrupts or interferes with the execution.
Even so, it is undeniable that allowing an outside individual in an execution room and allowing touching would increase the risk of a problem occurring, such as accidental or intentional disruption of or interference with the execution. So why can't the State choose to avoid any additional risk of disruption or interference, especially given the potentially catastrophic harm if the risked disruption or interference actually ensues?
That is a difficult question to answer, in my view. The core problem is that a State's understandable goal of avoiding a higher risk of great harm does not easily map onto the compelling interest/least restrictive means standards. In particular, it is difficult for a court applying those standards to know where to draw the line—that is, how much additional risk of great harm is too much for a court to order the State to bear.
Here, if the Court's own intuitive policy assessment that the State can reasonably tolerate the additional risk were all that the Court could muster in response to the State's argument, I might have concluded that the State could exclude religious advisors from the execution room, or at least could restrict their activities in the room and not allow physical touching, for example.
Importantly, however, the Court does not merely point to its own policy assessment of how much risk the State must tolerate in the execution room. The Court also relies in part on the history of religious advisors at executions. To be sure, the Court acknowledges that some of the history is not precisely on point because many executions historically were outdoor public hangings where the presence of religious advisors did not raise the same risks to safety, security, and solemnity that their presence in a small execution room does. And some of the other history involved state-employed chaplains, who arguably do not raise the same risks to safety, security, and solemnity as outsiders in the execution room. Still, the history generally demonstrates that religious advisors have often been present at executions.
And perhaps even more relevant, the Federal Government and some States have recently allowed inmates' religious advisors into the execution room. Those religious advisors have been allowed to engage in audible prayer and limited touching of the inmate without apparent problems. As the Court explains, experience matters in assessing whether less restrictive alternatives could still satisfy the State's compelling interest.
{Of course, in assessing risk, a government need not wait for the flood before building the levee. But as the Court explains, the recent experience in other States can nonetheless be somewhat informative in analyzing whether the State has a sufficiently compelling interest and has employed the least restrictive means of avoiding the risk of disruption or interference from the presence of religious advisors. Courts must be discerning, however, when relying on state practice. States are not necessarily required to follow the less restrictive practices of other States in a kind of race to the top (or bottom). Moreover, state practice can fluctuate as States change their approach to an issue over time. In any event, other States' practices nonetheless have sometimes informed judicial evaluation of whether a State's interest rises to the level of "compelling," and whether a State has employed the least restrictive means of achieving that interest.}
For some related though different thoughts on the subject by Justice Scalia, see his concurrence in Sable Communications v. FCC (1989), which struck down a ban on dial-a-porn. The government argued that the ban was the least restrictive means of serving a compelling interest in shielding minors from potentially psychologically damaging pornography, but the Court held that less restrictive means—such as requiring credit card payment, special access codes issued only after age screening, or scrambling with descramblers available only to adults—would be adequate to serve that interest. Justice Scalia agreed, but added:
It should not be missed that we are making a value judgment with respect to the indecency portion of the statute. The conclusion of the reasoning in Part IV of our opinion is as follows:
"For all we know from this record, the FCC's technological approach to restricting dial-a-porn messages to adults who seek them would be extremely effective, and only a few of the most enterprising and disobedient young people would manage to secure access to such messages. If this is the case, it seems to us that § 223(b) is not a narrowly tailored effort to serve the compelling interest of preventing minors from being exposed to indecent telephone messages."
We could as well have said:
"We know from this record that the FCC's technological approach to restricting dial-a-porn messages to adults who seek them would be inadequate, since some enterprising and disobedient young people would manage to secure access to such messages. Since this is the case, it seems to us that § 223(b) is a narrowly tailored effort to serve the compelling interest of preventing minors from being exposed to indecent telephone messages."
I join the Court's opinion because I think it correct that a wholesale prohibition upon adult access to indecent speech cannot be adopted merely because the FCC's alternate proposal could be circumvented by as few children as the evidence suggests. But where a reasonable person draws the line in this balancing process—that is, how few children render the risk unacceptable—depends in part upon what mere "indecency" (as opposed to "obscenity") includes. The more narrow the understanding of what is "obscene," and hence the more pornographic what is embraced within the residual category of "indecency," the more reasonable it becomes to insist upon greater assurance of insulation from minors. So while the Court is unanimous on the reasoning of Part IV, I am not sure it is unanimous on the assumptions underlying that reasoning. I do not believe, for example, that any sort of sexual activity portrayed or enacted over the phone lines would fall outside of the obscenity portion of the statute that we uphold, and within the indecency portion that we strike down, so long as it appeals only to "normal, healthy sexual desires" as opposed to "shameful or morbid" ones.
One can of course have different views of just how compelling the interest in shielding minors from pornography might be; but I think Justice Scalia's point about the less restrictive means inquiry is important.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Eugene, it looks as if that last paragraph is your commentary, not a quote of Justice Scalia...
Scrutiny is just lawyer feeling and mood at the time of the decision. It has no external validation.
Whoops, fixed, thanks!
The cynical / sarcastic part of me wonders if one way to get around this requirement for the pastor in the execution room would be to change execution to a stick of dynamite, inside a sturdily-built containment chamber. Surely, from a humane point of view, this is about as painless as can be. And I doubt many pastors would be willing to lay on hands.
Can't argue with that.
But I'd suggest a better way to do executions is to simply put them in a sealed bedroom on a bed and flood the room with nitrogen.
No pain, no struggles, the condemned simply drifts off to unconsciousness and dies.
Also fixes the pastor problem. Oh, I suppose you could equip him or her with a scuba tank.
Alternatively, you could tell the wardens running these executions that they can't just make up petty, arbitrary and unnecessary rules and restrictions at the last minute. You could also tell them that their post-hoc rationalizations will get the weight they deserve.
The guy being executed in this case is no saint but the prison officials seem to be doing everything they can to lower themselves to his level.
The State's excuse that this is just a delay tactic rings hollow when all they had to do was allow the minister in, within reason -- if the minister disrupted things, for example, then they could remove him.
The difficulty with having "compelling" in the statute is that, when used in a judicial context, it's clear who the object of the compulsion is -- a reviewing federal court. (Obvious, but the dilution of the standard in VMI "exceedingly persuasive justification" makes unambiguously clear that the scrutiny levels are referring to the people doing the scrutinizing.)
In the statute, however, it's not clear who should find the state interest compelling. A Federal court seeking to preserve constitutional rights within the federalist balance? A state court looking to vindicate its own law (within, incidentally, a state sovereignty arising from natural law and not a textual constitutional mandate)? Congress itself? The state executive? The common law? The commentators on the relevant area of law? The commenters on Volokh?
Mr. D.
Rest assured -- employees usually find in their employer's favor. Judges are government employees.
I don’t see this as a problem. State court judges are expected to apply the same standards as federal judges when applying federal law, and if they don’t the US Supreme Court can potentially review their judgments.
This is no exception. It works the same way any rule or standard in any federal law works. This is an argument, not against this specific rule, but against having a federal system. One can argue that state court judges, state officials, etc. can never apply federal laws fairly.
It’s just too late to entertain those kinds of arguments.
Ultimately the US Supreme Court sets the standard, although only in general, not in every detail in every possible case.
The question, though, is what "persuasive" is meant to encompass. When a federal court uses it, then, you're right, state courts can mimic that same calculus. But when Congress uses it, is "persuasive" meant to be composed of those things that Congress would find persuasive? Those things that the state decisionmaker would find persuasive? Those things that a federal court reviewing the situation on constitutional grounds would find persuasive? Those things a state court vindicating state law would find persuasive? Etc, etc.
Mr. D.
Corrigendum: Substitute "compelling" for "persuasive."
Mr. D.
Though perhaps not so intended, Justice Kavanaugh's analysis seems to expose the feeble nature of the tools we lawyers and judges have to argue for and decide the kinds of questions we are asked to argue for or decide. Maybe when we are trying to figure out whether to take on a question at all, we should pay more attention to our lack of useful tools to answer it.
Though perhaps not so intended, Justice Kavanaugh's analysis seems to expose the feeble nature of the tools we lawyers and judges have to argue for and decide the kinds of questions we are asked to argue for or decide.
Although it may seem brutally unfair to compare Justice Kavanaugh to Abraham Lincoln, here is a sample of what you get when you give the job to someone with the best tools:
To state the question more directly, Are all the laws but one to go unexecuted, and the Government itself go to pieces lest that one be violated? Even in such a case, would not the official oath be broken if the Government should be overthrown when it was believed that disregarding the single law would tend to preserve it?
That was Lincoln on July 4, 1861, explaining to Congress his suspension of habeas corpus. It stands as a specific example to illustrate a general principle inherent in the nature of government—that necessity may during an existential emergency justify the suspension of otherwise sacrosanct rights and laws.
Note that the standard for justification, as described by Lincoln, is existential peril, not less. My hope is that commenters here who in the case of a public health emergency have refused to recognize existential peril in an agency which deals death to more than a million, could reflect a bit on Lincoln's predicament, and the nation's. Try to answer the question of how you know, during an instance of pandemic deadly contagion, what the true extent of the peril may prove to be, until that extent has been shown by the actual end of the threat.
Of course, there was no existential peril in Lincoln's case; The US would have continued to exist if the Confederacy were permitted, it would have just had fewer states.
That is you judgment in hindsight, Bellmore. It was far from evident to Lincoln in 1861. Read the whole address.
I've read the address. You can hardly graduate from K-12 in this country without having read it.
Lincoln had his excuses for violating the Constitution. I'm not buying them, he was violating the right of habeus outside war zones, in areas where the court system was fully functional, in order to jail political dissidents.
The bottom line is that Lincoln was something of a tyrant, even if history has glorified him after the fact.
Lincoln did not need to arrest and hold without trial newspaper editors and mayors in friendly territory to conduct the war or protect the Union. At the very least trials could have been held.
I mean, the courts never stopped functioning during the war. There was no justification for the military arresting and holding people, in some cases up to two years, and then just releasing them down the road.
This is what you're trying to defend constantly on here, Stephen.
He will rule the way his masters want him to.
The reasoning will reflect one of three impulses - mumbles that try hide how silly some of these decisions are, trolls to 0wn the libs or setups to attack future policy. But it is effectively irrelevant, like the court is becoming.
Anyone ever get a hint on who, exactly, paid down his debt?
Yes.
It was him.
Safety and solemnity? Aren’t those risks TO the prisoner? So what if the minister is disruptive?
Do it again tomorrow. If this becomes a habitual issue, THEN institute a ban.
"In many areas of constitutional law, the Court allows a constitutional right to be overcome when a restriction passes "strict scrutiny"—i.e. (to oversimplify slightly), when the government can show that restricting the right is the "least restrictive means" of serving a "compelling government interest.""
From a policy standpoint this seems sensible, as long as "strict in theory" really IS almost always "fatal in practice". (In the case of disfavored rights, it's almost never fatal in practice.) From a strict textual standpoint, though... None of these rights appear to have "unless the government has a really good reason" clause.
That's why even Scalia has said he isn't a strict textualist. That is usually a strawman argument used by opponents of textualism. It's about what it is understood to mean, and if it is understood that a sufficiently strong justification can be excepted that it is what it means.
As Professor Volokh indicates in the article no one would understand the free exercise clause to require permiting a religion to engage in ritual human sacrifice. We know that the founders understood exceptions to the freedom of speech, like defamation. Not even the stongest 2nd amendment advocate would say that means someone must be allowed to own a nuclear bomb.
As I said, from a policy standpoint it makes sense, so long as you're genuinely strict about the scrutiny. Indeed, nobody supposes that human sacrifice would be protected by the 1st amendment, or infanticide by the emanations and penumbras of the right to privacy. [/sarc] The 1st amendment had a tacit assumption that it was reasonable religions that were being protected, not Bal worship or Thugee.
My own position is that the only reason that religion requires exemptions from generally applicable laws is that we have too damn many generally applicable laws to begin with: If you'd remotely consider allowing wine for Communion, for instance, then you never should have enacted Prohibition in the first place!
Religious liberty needs protection because we're unfree to begin with.
I was simply pointing out that practice and strict textualism co-exist in an uneasy truce, and that conflict erodes the law's adherence to the strict word of the Constitution, to our detriment. Exceptions should be few and far apart, and require massive grounding in founding era practice.
"If you'd remotely consider allowing wine for Communion, for instance, then you never should have enacted Prohibition in the first place!"
Relatively few people get drunk enough on communion wine to beat up their wives, kill people in car accidents, and so on.
"Relatively few people get drunk enough on
communionwine to beat up their wives, kill people in car accidents, and so on."So, why not outlaw beating up, killing, and so on, instead of the drinking? You'd never consider letting people do those things out of a religious motive?
Because you don't value liberty in the first place, and only grudgingly respect it if the demand has a religious basis?
Sigh. I wasn't arguing in favor of prohibition. I was disagreeing with the notion that an exception for communion wine undermines the arguments people made for prohibition.
"Because you don't value liberty in the first place, ..."
Sigh. You are unfairly demonizing proponents of prohibition.
Just for clarity: I would probably make current laws about alcohol looser, not tighter. But alcohol abuse does cause real world problems. The advocates of Prohibition didn't hate liberty, they thought that, on the balance, banning alcohol would make the world a better place. They were wrong about that, not evil.
"...and only grudgingly respect it if the demand has a religious basis?"
Sigh. I am about as not-religious as a person can be. I support religious accommodation on a practical basis. It is simply reality that religious people can have quite strong beliefs about things that matter not a whit to me. I can choose to issue cartridges greased with tallow and deal with the problem when my Sepoys mutiny, or I can use some other grease for the cartridges. To me, the latter course is preferable.
Yes, I don't think the proponents of Prohibition particularly valued liberty. Or, rather, they valued other things more highly.
" It is simply reality that religious people can have quite strong beliefs about things that matter not a whit to me."
My concern is that we do a fair job of policing the influence of religious beliefs over law, so it's fairly easy for the non-religious to simply ignore religious beliefs. And that's great!
But we do a simply terrible job of policing nominally non-religious beliefs in the same way. If you think X should be illegal because of religious doctrine, the obstacles to getting your way are high. If you think it should be illegal because of some irrational secular doctrine?
The wall of separation isn't even there, go for it!
Religion is hardly the only, or even in America the predominant, basis for attacks on individual liberty. It's just the only basis for such attacks that's formally barred.
For the sake of argument, I think it should allow you to own a nuclear bomb. I just imagine that insurance necessary would make it prohibitive for anyone who couldn't secure it at the level the government does.
If only there was a way to do this that didn't rely on ostensibly black & white questions like wheter strict scrutiny applies or not.
Maybe we should consult a biologist!
While I agree with you in the abstract, depending on one's position, if it's advantageous to frame it as black/white, its advocates will do so. If nuance helps, that will be the argument.
That is the problem with trans women participation in women's sports for example. The inability to confront the start reality that the physical advantage a biological male having gone through puberty cannot be fairly mitigated by hormone treatments as a young adult. That doesn't mean you can't use the preferred pronouns out of simple politeness. Yet for some that makes you a bigot.
Just bake the cake indeed.
It's both black & white and contextual whether such a unique class of people (trans women) can fairly be called women in all cases.
This is now an old post, and I don’t know if anyone will go back to it and see it.
There have been several major developments since the major pre-Smith cases.
First, until somewhat after the middle of the 20th century laws were more or less in alignment with mainstream religious views. Stores closed on Sunday by law; sex outside of marriage from fornication to sodomy was illegal; abortion was illegal; and so forth. The late 20th century was devoted to liberalization, repealing and in some cases striking down laws that mandated conformity to traditional mores sanctioned by religious norms.
There were isolated religious minorities that objected to various laws, sometimes major ones. The Amish objected to public high school and Quakers objected to the draft, for example. But these were small, isolated religions. At the beginning of rhe Civil Rights era, churches sprang up with segregation as a theological precept. And there was a time when it seemed this might result in a real church-state conflict. But these churches didn’t end up getting much traction. They made for a few legal cases as late as the 1970s. But they didn’t attract many members. They mostly faded away and didn’t have much practical impact.
The 21st century (it started somewhat earlier but wasn’t as visible) has seen something new: Mandatory laws - generally court-imposed - that directly contradict precepts of mainstream, widely held religions, and require large swathes of mainstream people to break religious divyates. This is fundamentally different from simply legalizing things that were previously illegal.
A second major development has been the increasing willingness of courts to declare compelling interests. There was once a clear, narrow conception of compelling interest: the survival of society and the state had to be implicated. War, plague, fire, and similar direct wide-spread threats to life implicating the existence of society as a going concern had to be involved. The debates of a century ago were phrased in those terms. Anti-communists characterized the threat of communist revolutikn as implicating the very existence of society, much like publicizing troop movements (or an ethnically Japanese fifth column). Right or wrong, at least the argument was phrased in traditional terms.
But “compelling interest” got looser and looser meanings, eventually to include anything the Justices felt especially strongly about. Perhaps the nadir was when the court assumed the state had a compelling interest in getting free contraceptives. One can see the evolution. Plague became public health, public health became anything associated with something doctors did, and voila. One can see the danger. Compelling interest permits prior restraints on speech, rounding people up and putting them in concentration camps without process. If that can be done for anything the court feels strongly about, or anything with some remote arguable relation to a traditional compelling imterest, and there may as well be no Bill of Rights at all.
A third development was perhaps a consequence of the general secularization of society. People started making up their own religions, and coming up with convenient ones. Whereas before conscientious objectors had to (and could) show a history of adherence to an objecting tradition, today people can simply have an epiphany, conclude a law is against their religion, and go to court.
All three developments make defining and enforcing boundaries between religious rights and state interests far more trracherous than in the past.