The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The Right to Defy Criminal Demands: Introduction
I've just finished up a rough draft of this article (6 years in the making), and I thought I'd serialize it here, minus most of the footnotes (which you can see in the full PDF). I'd love to hear people's reactions and recommendations, since there's still plenty of time to edit it. You will also be able to see all the posts, as they come up, here.
[* * *]
Craig is trying to force Danielle to do something, by explicitly or implicitly threatening to criminally retaliate if she doesn't go along. And, as often happens, Craig's threatened crime is endangering not just Danielle but also innocent bystanders.
Should the legal system require Danielle to comply with the demands, on pain of civil liability (for negligent injury or nuisance), or even of criminal punishment (for disturbing the peace or perhaps reckless endangerment)? Or should Danielle have, in effect, a right to defy Craig's demands, even if this means a higher risk to bystanders?
These questions can arise in many different situations:
- Danielle's abortion clinic has been firebombed in the past, by people who want it to close or at least to leave town. Neighbors sue the clinic, claiming its operation is a nuisance, because it makes them fearful that future attacks will harm them as well.[1] If the neighbors win, that in effect means that Danielle had a legal duty to comply with the arsonists' demands (at least to the extent of moving to a place that may be more expensive for her, and less convenient for patients).
- The clinic is indeed attacked again, and neighbors or visitors who are injured sue the clinic for negligently increasing the risk of such attack. The same can of course apply to any controversial business or enterprise, such as a church, synagogue, or mosque; an animal experimentation facility; a political organization; or a bookstore that sells books that contain the Mohammed cartoons or other material that highly offends some people.[2]
- A store is being robbed. Danielle, a store employee, refuses to go along with the robbers' demands that she turn over money, so they injure a customer to accentuate those demands. The customer sues the store, claiming the employee's actions foreseeably increased the risk of the injury. If the customer wins, that in effect means that Danielle had a legal duty to comply with the robber's demands.
- Craig kidnaps Danielle's employee, and demands ransom. Danielle refuses to pay, so Craig kills the employee; the employee's family sues Danielle for negligence, claiming that she had a duty to pay the ransom.
- Danielle and her fellow protesters carry signs insulting a religion. Craig and a group of his friends start throwing things at the protesters. The police order the protesters to leave, hoping to keep the confrontation from escalating,[3] and threaten to punish them with prosecution for breach of the peace or for resisting a lawful order if they don't comply.
A version of this problem also arises when Craig hasn't expressly demanded that Danielle do something, but rather Craig obviously doesn't want Danielle to do it:
- Danielle dances suggestively with a new lover in front of her estranged husband Craig (whom Danielle knows to be jealous). Craig shoots the lover, whose relatives sue Danielle for wrongful death, claiming her actions created a risk of injury by enraging Craig.[4] Again, their prevailing would mean that Danielle in effect had a duty to comply with Craig's implicit demands not to show romantic affection for others in front of him.
- Danielle lets her niece stay at her home, because the niece is fleeing Craig, the niece's violent estranged husband. Craig comes to Danielle's house to attack the niece and Danielle, and the gardener gets caught in the crossfire. The gardener's relatives sue Danielle for wrongful death, claiming her actions created a risk of injury by foreseeably enraging Craig.[5]
And a version of this problem arises with the "duty to retreat" that thirteen states still recognize in self-defense cases, and the more general "duty to comply with a negative demand" that seven states still recognize. These "duties" don't threaten criminal punishment or civil liability just for defying a criminal's demands (whether the demands are just "leave," as in the duty to retreat, or "stop doing X" in the duty to comply). But the "duties" do provide that a victim who refuses to go along with certain demands is stripped of her legal right to use lethal force in self-defense should such force be required.
- Danielle dances suggestively at a bar with a new lover in front of her estranged husband Craig. Craig demands that they stop, but they don't. Craig tries to knife Danielle, but she shoots him in self-defense. Danielle is then prosecuted, because state law provides that deadly force can't be used in self-defense if "[t]he actor knows that he can avoid the necessity of using such force with complete safety … by complying with a demand that he abstain from any action which he has no duty to take."
- A racist mob demands that Danielle leave the place where she lawfully is. She refuses, and she is attacked with deadly force; she defends herself with deadly force, and is then prosecuted because she failed to retreat.[6]
All these cases, I think, involve a tension between two approaches to the risk of retaliatory violence. We might call one approach the immediate pragmatism approach:
- The unfortunate reality is that a criminal is threatening to retaliate against some lawful action X.
- That reality creates serious risks to bystanders.[7]
- This pragmatic concern has a moral component: The bystanders have the right not to be unreasonably endangered.
- Even innocent victims of the threat thus have a duty to try to minimize such risks, even if that requires some constraint on their liberty.
And we might call the opposite approach the right to defy criminals' demands approach:
- Everyone has the right to act without having to obey criminals' demands (or criminals' expected wishes, which would in effect be implied demands).
- The law shouldn't step in on the side of the criminal by adding the threat of criminal liability, civil liability, or liability for self-defense to the criminals' threats.
- This moral concern has a pragmatic component: By giving legal force to the criminal's unlawful demands, the law would encourage more such unlawful demands.
- Even innocent bystanders should thus have no claim on the innocent victims that would require the victims to obey the criminals.
In some of these situations, this right to defy has been recognized (though not under that name). In others, the right has been rejected. In others, the matter is unsettled.
In this Article, I will try to chart the scope of this right, and the authority for and against it. To my knowledge, this is the first attempt to do so in a way that draws connection between these various areas; and I hope that showing these connections can more clearly illuminate the core principles underlying the right.
And I will argue that, on balance, such a right is sound: Generally speaking, the legal system should let people insist on their liberty, in the face of violent threats, and in the face of the danger that is therefore created by such defiance. Contrary to a claim often made in favor of the duty to retreat, the question isn't so much letting people preserve honor or reputation or "manliness," but letting them preserve liberty—freedom from domination by criminals—and the dignity that comes with such liberty.[8] Some may argue that this liberty and dignity comes at too high a cost, and ought to be restrained to protect bystanders, or even to protect the criminals. But whatever the right bottom line, we should acknowledge the cost of such a safety-first approach.[9]
To be sure, when our activities cause hazards to others, we often have to cease those activities, at least if the magnitude of the hazard is seen as "unreasonable." We are expected to avoid off-loading those hazards onto our neighbors or our visitors. Thus, for instance, if our commercial establishment attracts vermin that then go onto neighbors' land, and there's nothing we can do stop it, we might have to close up shop or move to an area where there are no neighbors nearby.
But if our establishment attracts criminal enemies who try to force us to stop operating, and in the process the criminals create a threat to our neighbors (whether as a deliberate tactic or just as a side effect of their attacks), we shouldn't have to close or move. To the extent our behavior is a but-for cause of the criminal hazard to our neighbors, that is a hazard that our neighbors should have to bear, as part of the common danger all of us face from criminals. It is the law's job to prevent crime, chiefly by deterring and incapacitating criminals. If the law instead arms our neighbors or the police with the right to stop our behavior when criminals so demand (through threat of civil liability or criminal punishment), the law is arming criminals with an extra weapon against us.
The legal system needn't worry about incentive effects on animals ("if garbage dumps have to move because they attract rats, this will give an incentive to rats"), but it should worry about incentive effects on humans (if abortion clinics have to close or move because arsonists threaten to burden them down, this will provide an incentive for such threats). And having to do things to prevent harmful animal incursions doesn't undermine our dignitary interests the same way that having to comply with human criminals' demands does.
In what follows, I hope to lay this out in more detail. I begin by discussing how a possible right to defy criminals arises as to negligence (Part I), nuisance (Part II), criminal law generally (Part III), and the duties to retreat and comply (Part IV). In Part V, I discuss possible limits on the right to defy: for instance, perhaps Danielle's behavior may still be punishable if it's independently wrongful (e.g., fighting words); if it has the specific purpose of provoking violence; if forbidding that behavior imposes only a modest intrusion on liberty (one possible rationale for a limited duty to retreat); if the behavior is legal but constitutionally unprotected; or if her defiance is unreasonable. Or perhaps even if Danielle's behavior may not be legally punishable, it should still lead to a lesser penalty for the criminal who is provoked by such behavior.
Finally, Part VI will ask whether it's legitimate for the law to require expensive precautions against threats, short of requiring compliance with criminal demands—for instance, by requiring threatened people or institutions to hire armed guards, put up physical barriers, or warn visitors or neighbors of the threat.[10] I think these precautions aren't as violative of the threat victims' dignity, because they don't enlist the state on the side of the criminal threatener. At the same time, courts and legislatures should be cautious about imposing such obligations, because they do let the threateners use the legal system to impose potentially massive costs on their victims. And, I'll argue, that is especially so when the duty is a duty to warn, which may intrude on the victims' privacy and lead people to shun them.
[1] These are roughly the facts of McBrayer v. Governors Ridge Off. Park Ass'n, Inc., 860 S.E.2d 58 (Ga. Ct. App. 2021), which led to a $1.5 million verdict in favor of the neighbors; the court of appeals reversed the verdict. I filed an amicus brief in this case on behalf of various law professors (including myself) and advocacy groups, urging reversal.
[2] Cf. Charlie Hebdo Shooting: Belgian Bookstores Selling Magazine Sent Warning Letters; Muslim Leaders Condemn New Magazine Issue, ABC News (Australia) (Jan. 14, 2015, 1:08 PM) ("'I recommend that you do not spread these cartoons of our beloved Mohammed in this despicable Charlie Hebdo magazine, at the risk of reprisals against you and your horrible business,' the letters said ….").
[3] See Bible Believers v. Wayne County, 805 F.3d 228, 239 (6th Cir. 2015) (en banc).
[4] This is based on Hurn v. Greenway, 293 P.3d 480 (Alaska 2013); see also Touchette v. Ganal, 922 P.2d 347 (Haw. 1996); Starr v. Gregory, No. 53-2004CA-000161, 2004 WL 5213002 (Fla. Cir. Ct. Polk Cnty. Oct. 19, 2004); John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Intervening Wrongdoing in Tort: The Restatement (Third)'s Unfortunate Embrace of Negligent Enabling, 44 Wake Forest L. Rev. 1211, 1217 (2009) ("A woman is aware of her ex-boyfriend's violent jealousy, as well as his occasional appearances at a bar located in their small town. She nonetheless agrees to meet a date for a drink at the bar. If her ex-boyfriend shows up and proceeds to pummel her date, she is subject to liability [under the Restatement (Third) of Torts.").
[5] Cf. Rojas v. Diaz, No. B144346, 2002 WL 1292996 (Cal. Ct. App. June 12, 2002).
[6] This is based on the facts of Laney v. United States, 294 F. 412 (D.C. Cir. 1923). The issue can arise even with solo racist attackers, see, e.g., Commonwealth v. Benoit, 892 N.E.2d 314, 327 (Mass. 2008) (concluding that self-defense was indeed unavailable in such a case).
[7] Even violent self-defense against the threatener, as in the last two examples, can create a risk to bystanders who might get caught in the shootout when the threatener responds, or in any future cycle of retaliation.
[8] In principle this would also apply to tortious demands: Say the abortion opponents in example 1 don't firebomb the clinic but instead just libel the clinic's neighbors, and the neighbors sue the clinic claiming that the clinic's continuing presence is a foreseeable cause of the libel; I'm inclined to say that there too the clinic shouldn't be held liable. But I'm not sure whether there would be libel liability in such a case. (Some libel cases allow lawsuits against an original libeler based on republication by third parties when such republication is "reasonably to be expected," Restatement (Second) of Torts § 576(c) (1977), but I've seen none that allow lawsuits against a nonlibeler whose actions foreseeably lead to libels.) And more broadly, it would be a rare scenario where a demand would be merely tortious and not criminal, and would at the same time threaten an innocent bystander in a manner for which the target of the demand would normally be legally liable.
[9] I don't claim that this dignitary interest is a general constitutional right as such (except in specific situations, such as speakers' or abortion clinics' refusal to obey shutdown demands). But I think it is a facet of liberty that the legal system ought to protect.
[10] See, e.g., Rocky Mountain Planned Parenthood, Inc. v. Wagner, 467 P.3d 287 (Colo. 2020).
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
The wrinkle for example 3 is whether the store’s formal or informal policy is to hand over the money.
Hey, Jerkoff. How about we kill the criminals after age 14, and end crime, instead? The lawyer protects the criminal because he generates lawyer make work and fees. How about we sue the lawyer profession for not killing the criminal after they damage the public? How about suing the police and their bosses the prosecutors for any crime after 3 strikes?
The lawyer profession dropped crime 40% with mandatory sentencing guidelines. That caused lawyer unemployment. So Scalia and his band went on a jihad against mandatory sentencing guidelines. Crime surged, and lawyer unemployment disappeared.
The Chinese fentanyl kills 100000 criminals a year. That repvents 200 crimes a year by each. Crime drops a lot. Now there is prison and bail reform. The murder rate soars 30%. The lawyer is satisfied and employed again.
How about rounding up the primary cause of crime, the hierarchy of the lawyer profession, trying them an hour? The sole evidence would be their legal utterances. Then shoot them in the court basement upon the verdict of guilty of insurrection against the constitution.
The lady has a signed judges order to keep her ex husband away. He shows up. The order is handed to the police. They refuse to interfere with ultraviolent thug. Husband kills the wife. Supreme Court says, no liability of the police, never mind total foreseeability.
The Supreme Court has granted self dealt immunity to the lawyer profession. Instead of liability to innocent victims, start with the liability of the primary cause of crime, the vile lawyer profession.
Take the damages out of the personal assets of the prosecutors and judges protecting and empowering the criminals.
Hey look, it’s the clown who can’t spell his own name spilling diarrhea all over his keyboard! Good to see ya.
Isn't this just a form of the Heckler's Veto?
Somebody needs to round up that guy Craig.
He always makes bail.
I ,understandably, do not like this article.
"Contrary to a claim often made against the duty to retreat, the question isn't so much letting people preserve honor or reputation or "manliness," but letting them preserve liberty—freedom from domination by criminals—and the dignity that comes with such liberty."
I think you meant "for."
Whoops, good point, thanks -- fixed.
For the displaying affection in front of estranged husband, a married person has a duty not to display sexual affection for others even behind the spouse’s back, and that duty was clearly breached here. And in general, it’s an analog of fighting words.
I think in general we may have what is essentially a somewhat broader, softer version of the fighting words doctrine here. Whether or not the conduct formally comes within the ambit of the doctrine, if one engaged in conduct which is considered provocative and highly socially disapproved, the state may not be able to stop you, but nonetheless one bears some responsibility for the consequences.
And I suspect this provides a fairly reliable way to classify the cases into those where a plaintiff can win and those where a plaintiff can’t.
Should conduct be socially disapproved? Once ipon a time a black person sitting in the front of a bus might start a riot. And today many would say proscriptions against adultery ought to be defiable without consequence. The abortion clinic perhaps represents the modern boundary case. It is considered provocative and highly socially disapproved by a substantial proportion of the population. Indeed, its protected status is under the chopping block in Dobbs.
In general I would say that if the state can proscribe something, it can make one liable to third parties for doing it if others are injured by reactions to it. Adultery laws were struck down by the 9th circuit but not by others, so I would say the spouse displaying a lover is still proscribable. And by this logic if Dobbs says states can ban abortion, the abortion clinic could be held liable.
Government can choose to decriminalize something but continue to hold those who do it civilly liable if 3rd parties are injured. It’s a policy option between the state itself banning something and the police enforcing it, and the state fully protecting it.
So for example since states can impose a duty to retreat, they could choose instead to say that if you don’t retreat we won’t charge you with a crime, but if 3rd parties are injured you’re liable. In general, if a state can ban something, it can instead take this intermediate step of not outright banning it but not fully protecting it either.
I think you've made a better argument against the 'fighting words' doctrine than an argument for extending it.
Despite that, I think the analogy is inapt. The 'fighting words' doctrine still includes a reasonable man reaction analysis. I have a choice to react when you insult me and my reaction will be measured against whether other reasonable people would agree that your insult was sufficiently provocative. In Prof Volokh's scenarios (and your subsequent analysis), you are imposing liability regardless of the reasonableness of my reaction to your threat of criminal action.
Do you mean if the state can proscribe something, or if the state actually has prescribed something? I hope the latter.
If it CAN prescribe something. Absolutely.
If the state can make something a crime, surely it can take the lesser step of making it a tort instead. It doesn’t have to enforce or punish maximally just because it can. Imposing 3rd party liability is just a variant of that.
Saying you can do something as long as nobody else gets hurt by it, but if somebody does get hurt, even if not directly by you, you’re liable for the hurt, is a completely rational intermediate position between saying something is absolutely forbidden and saying it’s completely permitted and your right to do it is fully protrcted.
It’s completely rational for a state to take an intermediate position between full prohibition and full protection. It’s a completely rational policy option.
If the state can fully prohibit something, it can instead take an intermediate position. There are a lot of possible intermediate options. This is only one.
There has always been a problem with a view of rational basis that doesn’t take into account the fact that humans aren’t always completely rational beings, and this has to be dealt with sometimes. Rationally, people ought never to get sick - it’s not fair, it’s not just, it’s arbitrary and capricious that some do and some don’t, yet they do.
It may likewise not be rational that certain other aspects of human behavior have biological bases and are subject to other parts of the brain besides the cerebrum. Yet it is so, and government sometimes has to take that into account.
Not sure where you're going with that, but it seems to me to be related to my disagreement with this:
The problem I have here is that when a criminal initiates a threat, it is after deliberation and planning, however minimal, which the victim does not have. The criminal chose the crime, the place, the time, and the victim. The victim has none of these luxuries and may have only a fraction of a second to make a decision on how to respond.
I have always thought of this as "original sin" and "foreseeable consequences". IANAL and I have no idea if there is some legal term for these, but they seem pretty obvious to me. Of course responses must be proportional; a bump in a crowd may be the original sin of a clumsy person which justifies pushing them away, a little, but it does not justify a lethal response or a knockout haymaker. A mugger should be responsible for an obviously frail victim's heart attack, but not necessarily a seemingly healthy 20-year-old's heart attack.
"The victim has none of these luxuries and may have only a fraction of a second to make a decision on how to respond."
I think the above has played into what I saw as a key driver behind 'castle' and 'stand your ground' laws. The basic unfairness of putting someone on trial who didn't initiate a conflict and was forced, under great stress, to respond within a narrow set of rules. The argument against that being that people who were accosted should be presumed innocent when they used lethal forms of self-defense and that it was up to the state to show that they acted unreasonably, as opposed to people having to proof their innocence to the state from the beginning, often (at least it was perceived that way) resulting in criminal trials.
Let’s focus on the women who came in with her lover in front of her husband. Are you really seriously intending to argue that husband’s reaction was deliberately planned? It’s a classic example of a “heat of passion” situation.
As alluded to before in characterizing the situation as a broadening of the “fighting words” doctrine, in cases where I think it’s at least arguably permissable for the law to create 3rd-party liability, the victim is doing something that has a tendency (or the proverbial “reasonable person” would characterize it as having a tendency) to provoke the conduct. And in cases where I think it’s definitely permissable, the state can make the provocative conduct itself illegal. If the state can make conduct illegal, I think it can always take the lesser step of not prohibiting it directly but holding the person who does it liable if a third party gets hurt as a result.
But in the cases where I think 3rd-party liability is valid, there is no premeditated crime against the victim. Instead, the crime is occurring as a result of some sort of heat-of-passion reaction to the victim’s provoking conduct.
Let’s focus again on the adulterous wife dallying with her lover in front of her husband. The husband here is (in applicable states) entitled to demand that the wife and/or lover stop. The demand in itself is not a criminal demand. He is not a criminal for making it in and of itself. In states with heart balm torts and similar laws, this demand can be enforced through the courts.
So if a state can make not doing something a legal duty and doing it a crime or tort, it should be very clear that instead of or in addition to any other civil or criminal enforcement of the duty the state can provide for, a state can provide that if a person violates the duty not to do something and further ignores a demand not to do it, that person can be held liable to third parties if violence erupts and third parties are hurt by the violence.
I said nothing about the husband and wife.
I'd think it would be up to a jury to decide the matter. There could be all sorts of related material. Were they separated, known to be having other affairs, had they declared their marriage an open one? Leave it to a jury.
It also needs to be proportional to the offence, even if just a fraction of a second.
This dilemma comes up traffic laws all the time.
Example: If Craig decides to run a red light as Danielle drives toward a cross section green light, she would have an obligation to yield in order to avoid recklessly plowing into him, even though she has the clear right away. Willfully endangering both parties by forcing her right and failing to avoid the wreck can be prosecuted.
What if the crime is malum prohibitum and/or of the "three felonies a day" variety? Does the same intuition apply?
The jealous ex case reminded me of a case out of Texas around a decade ago. Husband caught wife with another man. Wife cried rape! Husband shot man, who turned out to be the guy she was having a consensual affair with. Wife was convicted of manslaughter.
Within a few years in Texas there were also a couple cases where a father shot a guy about to rape his daughter in her bedroom only to find out that he was her secret boyfriend but she was afraid to admit it.
Note to self: No sex with married Texas women or underaged Texas girls. Bad for your health.
It has a long history. Lots of people got lynched in public for exactly this sort of conduct. The woman would cry rape because she didn’t want to admit to having a consensual relationship, especially an interracial one. And if she did admit to it, a lot of people wouldn’t believe her, or care.
" Or should Danielle have, in effect, a right to defy Craig's demands, even if this means a higher risk to bystanders?"
Yes, especially since Craig's demands almost certainly lack credibility. I mean, why would you rely on the word of a guy who says he'll do illegal stuff?
Re Recommendation: "No sex with married Texas women."
Got wife ? ... Forgot about the wife and her needs for consortium?
By way of more constructive comment: Public policy does actually favor sex with spouse in Texas (and elsewhere presumably too).
Adultery is still a fault-ground for divorce in Texas, but no longer a crime, and not actionable against the paramour.
Tex. Fam Code Sec. 6.003. ADULTERY. The court may grant a divorce in favor of one spouse if the other spouse has committed adultery.
TFC Sec. 1.106. CRIMINAL CONVERSATION NOT AUTHORIZED. A right of action by one spouse against a third party for criminal conversation is not authorized in this state.
TFC Sec. 1.107. ALIENATION OF AFFECTION NOT AUTHORIZED. A right of action by one spouse against a third party for alienation of affection is not authorized in this state.
Also, as far as civil remedies, tort damages are available for loss of lawful love (sex) services, but it appears that damages for loss of "spousal consortium" are not recoverable absent proof of physical injury. For concept definition, see Wal-Mart Stores, Inc. v. Alexander, 868 S.W.2d 322, 328 (Tex. 1993) (defining spousal consortium as the mutual right of the *husband and wife* to that affection, solace, comfort, companionship, society, assistance, and sexual relations necessary to a successful marriage)(stars added). So here, the marital relationship is recognized as special and meaningful.
More generally speaking, the absence of a criminal prohibition - or even of a civil cause of action - doesn't warrant the conclusion that the behavior in question is socially or morally desirable. Nor that it should be encouraged.
FILIUS NULLIUS ISSUE (FANCY FOR FATHERLESSNESS)
One obvious problem with nonmarital coitus (and corresponding legitimate state interest -- in legitimacy) is that no marital presumption of paternity is triggered based on the marital status of the mother if/when she gets pregnant and gives birth as a "feme sole".
But there are still several states that have the tort. Professor Volokh posted several years ago that North Carolina continued to have a lot of cases.
Moreover, a state needn’t criminalize conduct to impose 3rd-party liability. There are many intermediate policy options between criminalizing conduct and fully protecting it, and this is one of them.
It’s sufficient that a state CAN criminalize the conduct. If it can do that, it can impose 3rd-party liability in addition. Or it can impose it instead.
Dear Prof. Volokh,
I look forward to reading your paper, and offer some comments if I can think of something.
On first glance, minor technical point: I noticed that your PDF Document Meta Title does not match this article. It's "Overbroad Injunctions Against Speech (Especially in Libel and Harassment Cases)", a prior or concurrent (?) project: https://www2.law.ucla.edu/volokh/overinj.pdf
As a non-lawyer that finds this question fascinating, I thought of a nuance that was possibly not addressed in the analysis.
Does the analysis change if the direct victim's risk of negative consequences increases through compliance but the bystanders risk is increased by non-compliance?
Example: Craig accosts Danielle with a handgun on a crowded street demanding that she get into his vehicle. Danielle could decide her individual outcome is better if she runs because he could miss her if he shoots but getting into the car and hence his control gives him a guaranteed chance of harming her. The bystanders would be safer if she gets into the car but at risk if she runs and he shoots.
Your example would create a duty of heroism, and that would never fly. It would require you to literally jump on the grenade, to borrow a common example of heroism.
Absent a special relationship (like parent-child or property owner-invitee), you have no obligation to protect others from the criminal acts of a third party.
Let's say I kiss Craig's ex, abort his baby, or whatever. Craig snaps. Innocent third parties come after me. Under what circumstances do I get to pass the liability off to Craig? Are we joint tortfeasors subject to the laws governing them? Do I have to name him as a third party defendant and let the jury partition blame? Is he a necessary or indispensable party? If he is not a party, can I come after him later to recover my losses? (Obviously he would have been sued if he were rich, but maybe I got a tip that he got a seven figure offer for his life story or won the lottery or something.)
Trolley torts. Or perhaps that should be troll-y torts. There is a very important distinction between a claim being morally right and a claim sounding in Tort. Negligence itself only worms its way into the thicket of legitimate causes of action because of the state's interest in enforcing a discrete duty of care. Absent a duty of care, the actions might unleash yuge Krakkens, but a court has no legitimate authority to hear the case. Statutes govern, not Torts.
(Or Tortz, as the law French sometimes had it, which really should be the name of the law school course.)
Mr. D.
1
I agree with the idea that individuals have a right to defy criminal demands made by the government or law enforcement. This right is based on the principle of individual liberty and the belief that individuals should not be forced to act against their will, especially when it comes to matters of conscience. However, it is also important to note that this right comes with consequences, and individuals should be prepared to accept those consequences for their actions. It is up to the courts to decide on a case-by-case basis whether the right to defy criminal demands is justified in a particular situation.