The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The Bureaucrat in Chief
Behind the technicalities of the appointment and removal power is a difficult tradeoff between democratic accountability and impartiality in implementing laws.
This is the second post in this series based on my new book, Contested Ground: How to Understand the Limits on Executive Power. I'm grateful to the editors for giving me the opportunity to speak to this audience. Today's topic is presidential control of the executive branch.
We usually think of the "bureaucracy" as a creature apart from the President. But one of the President's most important roles is to manage the bureaucracy, mostly through top-level political appointees or the sub-bureaucracy that is the Executive Office of the President. Nearly everybody important in the executive branch can be fired by the President at will. As readers of this blog know, it's the "nearly everybody" that's the sticking point. Are exceptions like independent agencies constitutional, or does everybody significant in the executive branch have to serve at the President's will?
Believers in the unitary executive argue that the original understanding dictates an unlimited presidential removal power. It's probably not necessary to rehash their arguments for readers of this blog. For some reason, the unitary executive theory has become associated with conservatism. That seems to me to be historically contingent. Liberals like FDR certainly thought the unitary executive was a better way to implement progressive policies.
It's also a bit puzzling that people who support the unitary executive tend to be people who also support a strong nondelegation doctrine. It's not that these positions are inconsistent but they do seem to be in some tension. Supporters of the unitary executive often argue that subordinates should heed the President's policy agenda. The idea of the nondelegation doctrine, however, is that the executive shouldn't have major authority over major regulatory policy—those decisions should all be made by Congress. It seems a bit incongruous to advocate presidential power to set the executive branch's policy agenda while on the other hand denying that the executive branch should have a policy agenda in the first place.
I'm also puzzled by the argument that centralizing all executive authority in the White House protects liberty. You could easily make the argument that the rights of people regulated by the government would be better protected by providing a bit of insulation of decisionmakers from partisan politics. Indeed, that seems to me in some ways a more natural position for conservatives to take, in the interests of protecting property rights and liberty. If history had gone a little differently, we might well have seen liberals adopting the unitary executive and conservatives defending independent agencies—that just doesn't happen to be the way things have worked out.
The presidential removal power may be the issue of presidential power where the debate has focused most heavily on the original understanding. Today's Supreme Court has moved sharply in the President's direction on this issue, insisting that the original understanding settles the issue. Originalists can certainly muster evidence in favor of the unitary executive, evidence the current majority on the Supreme Court seems to find conclusive.
The historical record doesn't strike me as nearly so clear. One the key events involved the first office established by Congress, the Secretary of State. The upshot of the debates left the power of removal with the President, but the proceedings were confused and it's not at all clear that a majority endorsed the unitary executive as a constitutional matter. (A recent paper by Jed Shugerman and Jed Handelsman takes a close look at the evidence.)
In some ways, the most striking thing is that there was any dispute about the issue. Today, we would think of the Secretary of State as the epitome of the kind of official who should be removable by the President: a cabinet official whose duties center on foreign affairs, an area in which presidential prerogatives are near their peak. Yet it seems to have been less clear then than today.
In short, if we are looking for a clear shared understanding of the constitutional issue in 1790, there doesn't seem to have been one.
If we look earlier in history, recent research by Daniel Birk has shown the King's power over officials was in some ways surprisingly limited. Many officials were removably only by other officials or local magistrates, not by the King, and the King did not have the power to direct many officials in their duties. Indeed, some appointments were for life or were even hereditary. The King was nonetheless clearly thought to be vested with the executive power. That makes it harder to claim that vesting the executive power in the President necessarily meant that underlings are mere sock-puppets carrying out orders.
Based on this history, I find it hard to maintain that the constitutional text, as understood in the Framing period, precludes all limits on presidential removal of officers. In some ways, the non-originalist argument for presidential removability may be stronger—or at least for a strong presumption of presidential removability. It's true that there have been exceptions, such as the Civil Service, independent agencies, and a few others such as the post-Watergate Independent Counsel.
If we step back and ask what rule would be most appropriate in a democratic republic, history suggests a good deal of agreement with supporters of the unitary executive. Whether for constitutional reasons or otherwise, high-level officers nearly all serve at the pleasure of the President. "Unitarians" have some persuasive policy arguments on their side. They argue that unitary presidential control provides energy and coherence in government policy, while also making political accountability for decisions clear.
These are powerful arguments, but they don't necessarily dictate a universal rule of presidential removability. Sometimes, other values may be more pressing: ensuring that people get fair hearings from impartial administrative officers, ensuring that financial regulation isn't exploited for partisan advantage, and making sure that the government is efficiently administered rather than serving only as a source of cushy jobs for political loyalists.
You could make a reasonable textualist argument that these policy decisions are solely in the hands of Congress, given its power to make laws necessary and proper to carrying out the duties of the executive branch. As a non-originalist, however, I think both historical practice and Supreme Court precedent foreclose that position. It also seems to me that unlimited congressional control would unbalance government power too much in favor of the legislative branch.
In the book, I leave to the reader to reach a judgment about the right approach. My own views are that I see no reason to think that existing exceptions to presidential removability are unconstitutional. On the other hand, outside of the types of positions covered by existing practice, I'd want to see some cogent arguments about why officials performing specific functions need special protection from removal.
[Next up: the non-delegation doctrine.]
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
"It's also a bit puzzling that people who support the unitary executive tend to be people who also support a strong nondelegation doctrine. It's not that these positions are inconsistent but they do seem to be in some tension."
I don't see the tension. All authority of the executive branch is the President's authority, but this doesn't speak to the extent of that authority, only who possesses it.
In fact, nondelegation doesn't merely imply that a branch can't delegate the exercise of its own powers to another branch, but also that it can't delegate the exercise of a co-equal branch's powers to somebody other than the one possessing those powers.
"I'm also puzzled by the argument that centralizing all executive authority in the White House protects liberty. You could easily make the argument that the rights of people regulated by the government would be better protected by providing a bit of insulation of decision makers from partisan politics."
But partisan politics are HOW the voters protect their liberties, voting out those who'd attack them. Placing those powers in the hands of people who can't be voted out of office places their abuses beyond the voters' capacity to punish.
"“I’m also puzzled by the argument that centralizing all executive authority in the White House protects liberty."
Indeed, Brett has the right idea here. The alternative is putting power and authority into the hands of unelected executive officials who can't be removed from their office.
Imagine if for example, the Secretary of Homeland Security was kept over from the Trump Administration, and couldn't be removed by Biden. They would continue more aggressive deporting policies. Biden would tell the Secretary to change the policy, and the Secretary would simply go "No".
Exactly right. I might think Biden is violating his "take care" obligation by his determination to systematically refuse to enforce our immigration laws, but that's for the voters to deal with, not some bureaucrat.
Distributed power is fundamentally less authoritarian than centralized power.
This is such a fundamental of political science, the Founders knew it 250 years ago. Check out the discussions about having 2 Presidents at the Founding for exactly that reason.
And populism has it's uses, but the argument that populism makes for more liberty is not factual.
Not if it's distributed to people that you have no leverage over, because they're basically impossible to fire, and not up for election.
This is the essential structure of the European Union, specifically its Commission, which structurally is accountable to no other organ of government in the way of parliamentary democracy or our American system of regular elections. Of course the Commission can be shamed politically by leaders of its member states, but often they have little recourse in the democratic sense. This is really by design, with European elites historical fear of nationalism. But it's also fundamentally undemocratic and apparently the desired goal of many American technocrats.
I don't think you have that right - the EU is still pretty nationally federated.
The powers of the Commission on it's own are really limited, and their decisions need to be ratified by consensus. They have no research budgets, for instance, and need each nation to sign onto any collaborative initiative.
It's more like the Articles of Confederation than anything.
Really, I think you're confusing theory and practice.
I am speaking from the practice of basic research and space initiatives in the EU.
As usual, you assume no professionalism in people.
By your logic, the judiciary was created as a tyrannical monster. And so was the original Senate. Populism is not the only method of accountability or internal control.
Distributed power means authoritarianism requires a level of coordination and consensus that is unrealistic in any large group. Centralized power has no such check.
You would have a rotating dictatorship, so long as it was elected. The Founders were vastly wiser than that.
Yes, I assume that bureaucrats, too, are human beings, not angels. I gather you object to this.
You assume they are all devils. That if someone is insulated from firing, they will immediately become authoritarians.
I'm saying that's not true; I have the broad thesis about civil servants - yours is the extreme one.
"Distributed power is fundamentally less authoritarian than centralized power."
Depends on the conditions of the power.
Imagine on one hand executive power centralized in a single person, but whom has constitutional limits on his power, and who needs to be re-elected every 4 years.
Imagine on the other hand an military junta which shares power, but doesn't have any real constitutional limits and doesn't need to be re-elected every 4 years.
By any real consideration, the military junta is more authoritarian, despite the "power" being more "distributed".
"All authority of the executive branch is the President’s authority. . . ."
I'm not so sure.
Art II, Sec 2, ". . . but the Congress may by law vest the appointment of such inferior officers, as they think proper, in the President alone, in the courts of law, or in the heads of departments."
"Heads of Departments"
So what does that mean?
Congress could appoint a Secretary of State but not have that person be accountable to the President?
Congress can't nominate/appoint but it can by statute let lesser officials pick certain other lesser officials. The President can veto such a law.
That provision says nothing about authority or removal though. The President can therefore control and also remove any such appointments.
The key wording there is "inferior officer"
These are positions that don't have true policy making power. The Secretary of State, for example, is not an inferior officer. The Secretary of State is a principal officer, and must be appointed by the President.
The Deputy Secretary of State by contrast answers to the Secretary of State, and would be considered an inferior officer. They "could" be directly nominated by the Secretary of State (if Congress so wished). Usually that's high enough up that they aren't. But under the Deputy Secretary of State are several other inferior officers that Congress may allow the Secretary of State to appoint.
That makes sense. Thanks.
He explained the tension: if the executive branch has no policy discretion, then why does it matter how that lack of policy authority is allocated within the executive branch?
The King was nonetheless clearly thought to be vested with the executive power.
I am curious about that. The answer varies depending on what period the question is meant to cover. It was true in the early 17th century; it is not true now. I have long thought it was an interesting question whether the so-called tyranny of King George III over the colonies was in fact more a tyranny of the Parliament over them. I have wondered if, as a matter of practice, the colonists with their petitions were trying to get protection from a King who was powerless to provide it—with all or most of that power already under the practical control of Parliament.
I am poorly informed about 18th century English politics. I would welcome information from anyone who can make the case, one way or the other.
"it is not true now"
It is technically true even now. The ministers of the Crown act in the name of the Queen. Certain executive functions remain in the Queen's sole authority [like honors and peerages] but she is advised by the prime minister.
"I have wondered if, as a matter of practice, the colonists with their petitions were trying to get protection from a King who was powerless to provide it—with all or most of that power already under the practical control of Parliament."
That period of time is a grey area. One of the large turning points was the English Bill of Rights of 1689. This sharply limited the unilateral power of the King.
After this however, besides the power of Royal Proclamation, one of the major powers of the King was to select the prime minister he wanted, who would go along with his desired policies. If the King wanted war with the colonies, he'd pick a PM who would agree with him. The PM didn't necessarily need a majority in parliament.
I'm with Brett here.
The two areas (nondelegation and unitary executive) aren't in tension at all.
The entire concept is that ultimately the people who make the policies should be voted in by the people, and answer to the people.
You can't give away your power to unelected officials. And the person in charge of the executive branch is voted in...it's not an unelected Secretary of State making policy that the President can't remove.
If officials within the executive branch are not responsible to the President, are they in the executive branch? If not, what branch are they in? In a democracy, they should be responsible to somebody. It may be a good idea in principle to allow bureaucrats tenure across administrations, but that doesn't make it constitutional.
More recently, Joe Biden (or his handlers) has been acting on unitary-executive principles, by firing certain officials he wants to replace, with no regard to those officials' statutory terms of office. (The general counsel of the NLRB comes to mind, as do members of boards of visitors of the service academies.) Those officials weren't members of "quasi-legislative" or "quasi-judicial" bodies, so their firing didn't technically violate the rule of Humphrey's Executor.
How many branches of the federal government are there? Three, and only three. Not 4, not a dozen, not undefined. Any power purporting to be exercised outside of one of the three is unconstitutional, ipso facto.
And yet, unsurprisingly, each of the alphabet soup agencies promote a myth of their supposed "independence." It's unsurprising that individuals and institutions aggrandize their own power and importance to the maximum extent possible. That's natural and expected.
"It's also a bit puzzling that people who support the unitary executive tend to be people who also support a strong nondelegation doctrine. It's not that these positions are inconsistent but they do seem to be in some tension..."
They are only in tension if you assume that someone must be a maximalist or minimalist in all things concerning presidential power, or if you assume fully partisan or self-interested short term motivations.
Put another way, the supposed "tension" reflects nothing more or less than the founding design of separated powers, republican representation, and ambition being made to counteract ambition, all for the cause of liberty and restraint of government.
"I'm also puzzled by the argument that centralizing all executive authority in the White House protects liberty. You could easily make the argument that the rights of people regulated by the government would be better protected by providing a bit of insulation of decisionmakers from partisan politics."
And these supposedly unbiased regulators are surely "angels in the form of kings," right? That is who resides in the massive bubble known as Washington DC that lives remarkably well off the people's tax revenues and money printing?
One can "easily make the argument" for monarchy, or all sorts of things. I appreciate a wide ranging discussion.
"Originalists can certainly muster evidence in favor of the unitary executive, evidence the current majority on the Supreme Court seems to find conclusive.. The historical record doesn't strike me as nearly so clear. . . In some ways, the most striking thing is that there was any dispute about the issue."
I don't think it should be surprising that there was partisan jockeying and testing of basic constitutional structures right from the start. But how does that inform the textual meaning of "The executive power shall be vested in a President.." The link seems to point to the Necessary and Proper clause. So the executive power is vested in the President, except when Congress finds it necessary and proper to vest it elsewhere?
"Sometimes, other values may be more pressing: ensuring that people get fair hearings from impartial administrative officers, ensuring that financial regulation isn't exploited for partisan advantage, and making sure that the government is efficiently administered rather than serving only as a source of cushy jobs for political loyalists."
Again with the benevolent philosopher king unelected bureaucrats. There's no apparent reason why these values are necessarily in opposition to a unitary executive. There's no reason why a self-serving permanent bureaucracy, increasingly untethered from any elected representative, could not be far worse an ensuring fair hearings, exploiting financial regulation, or ensuring efficient administration rather than cushy jobs for loyalists. The argument here is just one of "who" and "whom." In the words of Humpty Dumpty, "which is to be master—that's all."
There are examples of state administrative agencies at the Founding that were not unitary. KY, MD, and PA all allowed substantial legislative control over the allocation of decisional authority within their executive branch.
There is no evidence the Constitution sought to depart from that regular understanding of the executive power.
You can cry about how civil servants are unelected, but the Constitution is far from a populist document.
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1614&context=jcl
Many states do things differently. They even have elections for Secretary of State, Attorney General, and more, which can allow for the AG to be of a different party from the Governor.
The US Federal Government does not have those elections. The first sentence of Article 2 of the US Constitution is "The executive Power shall be vested in a President of the United States of America"
Not "A President and his cabinet", but "a President".
The regular practice at the Founding goes to original public meaning.
If the Feds wanted to have their executive power function differently, they would have said it.
That simply untrue, because you're comparing apples to oranges. If state constitutions divide executive power between elected officials, that says nothing about the U.S. Constitution vesting it in a single elected official. Just because competing arrangements existed during/immediately after the founding era does not inform an original meaning of federal executive power.
Now if you could find an example mirroring the U.S. Constitution, with similar wording yet a historical record of divided executive authority, then could argue against the unitary executive theory.
At the Founding, the state exercise of executive power would have been something everyone knew about, including the drafters of the Constitution.
So when they use a nebulous term like 'the executive power' looking at how existing governments in America understood that term tells you what how the pubic the Drafters were writing for would have understood the term.
If the were creating a competing arrangement, they would have been more directive. But they were not, so it is safe to assume that existing arrangements were within their expectations.
I'm no originalist, but neither is the unitary executive.
It was actually directly discussed....
The phrase "unitary executive" was discussed as early as the Philadelphia Convention in 1787, referring mainly to having a single individual fill the office of President, as proposed in the Virginia Plan. The alternative was to have several executives or an executive council, as proposed in the New Jersey Plan and as promoted by Elbridge Gerry, Edmund Randolph, and George Mason.[8][9]
They went with the Virginia plan.
Gaslightro fails again....
This is not what ML is arguing for in his OP.
I'd say it's not what anyone thinks about when they talk about the unitary executive in since the Bush admin.
Your argument is far from persuasive or coherent. There were, and are, all kinds of differences among states in how they do things. In fact, many states do not have a unitary executive. They have a plural executive.
That the federal constitution creates a "unitary executive" isn't really up for debate. It certainly is originalist, and non-originalists agree as well. The debate however is over the interpretation of this unitary executive, in stronger or weaker versions.
If you have an argument about what the "executive power" means then you might explain it, but whatever scope you give to that term, keep in mind that anything you define as outside of the scope is going to be "legislative power."
That the federal constitution creates a “unitary executive” isn’t really up for debate. It certainly is originalist, and non-originalists agree as well. The debate however is over the interpretation of this unitary executive, in stronger or weaker versions.
You're wrong. You're just so deep in ideology you're flirting with solipsism. Unless you have some idiosyncratic definition of unitary executive, that's still a controversial idea.
If you have an argument about what the “executive power” means then you might explain it, but whatever scope you give to that term, keep in mind that anything you define as outside of the scope is going to be “legislative power."
An executive employee that can only be fired for cause is not a legislative power.
"According to law professors Lawrence Lessig and Cass Sunstein, "No one denies that in some sense the framers created a unitary executive;"
Unless you're Gaslightro...
Did you read the paper I linked, AL?
And read the paper you're quoting, not just (I assume) a wikipedia take.
http://www.pegc.us/archive/Authorities/Lessig_Col_L_R_President.pdf
Here is the cite for the sentence you quoted: "While it was understood that there would be departments responsible for daily administration, the Convention clearly and consciously chose a single and independent executive over a collegial body subject to legislative direction"
So quit saying I'm a liar, and maybe click on what you're citing before slamming 'submit.'
Which is not what anyone these days is talking about when they talk about the unitary executive.
Is it what you mean, AL? Are you defending the idea that the President is a single individual
…
You keep saying "king" as an epithet, but the vision of executive power of Trumpkins expressed over the last four years was that the president was an actual king, vested with complete discretion as to what the executive branch could do and answerable to nobody in his personal or professional capacity, with the only check on him being impeachment — and that only sort of.
Couldn't be investigated. Couldn't be prosecuted. Not even by state officials for state offenses. Not even for acts that took place before he became president. Couldn't be impeached no matter what he did in office unless it constituted a criminal offense. Could prevent anyone in the executive branch from testifying or supplying any information to Congress. Could make up his own foreign policy, even in the face of laws to the contrary. Could use his office for personal political gain, unless (maybe) that use actually violated the law — and again, even then, the only remedy would be impeachment, not prosecution.
(We won't even get into the Eastman theory that his own crony, the Vice President, could unilaterally decide whether the president would be reelected.)
That's quite a whatabout and intentional side step of any point I was touching on.
As you probably know, the first reference you targeted is a Jefferson quote, and the second is Plato.
Plato's utopian supposition was that by becoming extremely wise, the philosopher would be fit to be king, as in his utopian city of Kallipolis. Jefferson on the other hand looked back and asked wryly - addressing those who questioned the idea of self-government - whether Plato's utopian leader had yet been found in history.
My criticism is directed toward the idea that a mass of unelected bureaucrats must necessarily be less venal than a President. For the people who take this position, I suspect the real thinking is, "the mass of unelected bureaucrats tend to agree with me (and I may be one of them), so I'd like to permanently vest power there, rather than in a single office that is in danger of being subject to (potentially free and fair) popular elections every 4 years."
But taking a step back with the politics out of it, I guess the same criticism would apply to an argument over being governed solely by a mass of unelected bureaucrats with splintered authority, versus an actual king.
Should nurses and teachers with demonstrated natural immunity to COVID, and high demonstrated antibody levels be allowed to work in hospitals and schools without vaccination?
Why or why not?