The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Tyler Cowen on "State Capacity Libertarianism" I: Is it the Wave of the "Smart" Libertarian Future?
Is "state capacity libertarianism" really where "smart" libertarians are headed? I am skeptical.
In a much-discussed recent blog post, economist Tyler Cowen advocates what he calls "state capacity libertarianism" (which I will call "SCL" for short). He makes two claims: that "state capacity libertarianism" is the view that "the smart classical liberals and libertarians" are already moving towards even as traditional libertarianism is in decline, and that SCL is the right world-view for libertarians to adopt.
Tyler's mini-manifesto has already attracted insightful responses from David Henderson, John McGinnis, Vincent Geloso and Alex Salter, Nick Gillespie, Henry Olsen of the Washington Post, and John Cochrane. But I think there is more to be said.
In particular, it's important to emphasize that Tyler's normative argument is distinct from his positive claim about what libertarians are actually doing. One can be right even if the other is wrong.
Although I'm a big fan of Tyler's work, I am skeptical about both the normative and the positive aspects of his case for SCL. This post takes up the positive issue. I will cover the normative one in a subsequent piece.
Here's Tyler's positive analysis of where libertarians have been headed over the last few years:
Having tracked the libertarian "movement" for much of my life, I believe it is now pretty much hollowed out, at least in terms of flow. One branch split off into Ron Paul-ism and less savory alt right directions, and another, more establishment branch remains out there in force but not really commanding new adherents…. For another, smart people are on the internet, and the internet seems to encourage synthetic and eclectic views, at least among the smart and curious. Unlike the mass culture of the 1970s, it does not tend to breed "capital L Libertarianism." On top of all that, the out-migration from narrowly libertarian views has been severe, most of all from educated women….
Along the way, I believe the smart classical liberals and libertarians have, as if guided by an invisible hand, evolved into a view that I dub with the entirely non-sticky name of State Capacity Libertarianism."
Tyler's definition of state capacity libertarianism is not a simple one. But, in so far as it differs from previous versions of libertarianism, it largely boils down to a focus on expanding and improving the quality of government, including performing at least some substantial range of functions that most libertarians have traditionally argued should be left to the private sector.
Both the claim that there is an outmigration from libertarianism and the claim that "smart" libertarians are turning towards SCL strike me as wrong, or at least unsupported by the available evidence. Here's why:
I. Is there an Outmigration from Libertarianism?
Has libertarianism experienced a large outmigration to "alt right directions?" We can certainly find examples of notorious alt rightists who used to be (or at least used to claim to be) libertarians. But none of them were actually at all prominent within the libertarian movement, and there is no indication they are a large group of people (even relative to the total number of libertarians out there).
It is also fair to point out that there have long been some libertarian-leaning people who are sympathetic to various types of right-wing nationalism and have tried to make alliances in that quarter. But this is not a new problem, and such people have long been condemned by the majority of the libertarian intellectual community. The issue actually came to public prominence in 2008 and 2012 during the controversy over Ron Paul's 1990s racist newsletters, at which time numerous prominent libertarians condemned them.
The genuinely prominent defectors from libertarianism in recent years, have actually gone not to the right, but to the center and left. The most notable are probably Jerry Taylor, Will Wilkinson, and some of their associates at the Niskanen Center. I took issue with Taylor's rejection of "ideology" here, and Wilkinson's views on democracy and libertarianism here and here. Taylor and Wilkinson are important figures, and we should take their critiques of libertarianism seriously (as I have tried to do). But, so far at least, their shift has not triggered a more general exodus from libertarianism.
Various measures of the number of libertarian-leaning voters in the general public show that their numbers are roughly the same as they were 15-20 years ago (somewhere between 8 and 20 percent, depending on which measures you use). The number of self-conscious, rigorously consistent libertarians is surely much smaller. But the same can be said for adherents of other ideologies. Many studies show that most voters don't take a carefully consistent and rigorous approach to political ideology, and often don't even understand the basics of those world-views.
I don't know of a good measure of the number of libertarians in the intellectual world, such as in academia or policy analysis. Quantitative studies of academic ideology (at least those I am familiar with) fail to differentiate libertarians from other non-left scholars. But my admittedly anecdotal impression is that the percentage is at least as high as a decade or two ago, and perhaps modestly higher. In my own academic field (law), there are more libertarians now than when I started my career in 2003.
Finally, I see no evidence that there has been a "severe"outmigration by "highly educated women." There is no doubt that self-identified libertarians are disproportionately male, and this is a problem for the movement (by contrast libertarians are much more racially and ethnically diverse than many think). But this is not a new problem, and has not gotten worse in recent years than it was before.
If anything, the percentage of women among younger libertarian intellectuals strikes me as higher than that in my own generation and those that came before. This is another point on which we lack systematic data, so I could be wrong. But the percentage of women in groups such as Students For Liberty (I have spoken at several of their conferences) is much higher than that in libertarian groups I saw when I was a student in the 1990s. Ditto for the percentage of women among younger libertarian academics in law, economics, and political science (the fields I am most familiar with).
It's also worth noting that virtually all the prominent defectors from libertarianism in recent years have been men, not women (Taylor and Wilkinson are, again, notable examples). Though, in fairness, that's in substantial part because there were more men in the initial population.
Perhaps Tyler's claim of an exodus can be defended on the ground that it only applies to "narrow" libertarianism, as he puts it. Much depends on what counts, as "narrow." But if that term means categorically rejecting all government intervention beyond the most strictly defined minimal state or endorsing absolute property rights that can never be overcome by any other considerations, then most libertarian thinkers already rejected those views a decade or two ago. That was certainly true of nearly all who were at that time prominent in the academic and intellectual worlds. Perhaps even more have rejected that position since then. But if so, it's not a major trend.
It is, I think, more useful to define libertarianism as the ideology that has a very strong presumption against government intervention in both the "economic" and "social" spheres, and therefore rejects a very high percentage of the activities of modern states. By that definition, there has been no major exodus to speak of.
Thus, Tyler is, I think, wrong to claim that there has been a substantial exodus from libertarianism in recent years. That does not mean libertarians can afford to rest on our (very modest) laurels. Far from it. After all, it is also clear there has been little, if any, significant expansion of the libertarian movement in that time. Our position has also weakened because of the rise of nationalism on the right and "democratic socialism" on the left, both of which are deeply inimical to libertarianism. Even if the number of libertarians has not declined, we face more hostility from adherents of other ideologies than was the case 10-20 years ago.
A group that was a small minority to begin with needs to more than just maintain its position. It badly needs growth. On that point, I very much agree with Nick Gillespie's response to Tyler's post.
II. Are "Smart" Libertarians Adopting SCL?
What of Tyler's claim that "the smart classical liberals and libertarians" have moved towards SCL? A lot here turns on who qualifies as "smart." If it means those who have the highest IQ or other forms of raw intellectual ability, then we don't have the evidence we need to figure out the answer. Who knows whether the libertarian intellectuals who agree with Tyler's position are smarter - in this sense - than those who don't?
It may be more productive to interpret "smart" as referring to the most prominent and successful libertarian thinkers. The quality and reach of thinkers' ideas surely matters more than how high their IQs are.
Consider those American libertarian thinkers whose work has had the biggest mainstream impact over the last decade, as measured by both public and academic attention. The three cases that most stand out are Jason Brennan's work on democratic theory and related issues, Bryan Caplan's work on education and immigration, and Deirdre McCloskey's series of books on the nature and history of liberalism. Little if any of their work focuses on enhancing state capacity. To the contrary, all three emphasize the case for limiting and constraining government power, albeit in quite different ways.
The same is true for nearly all the most notable recent libertarian scholarship in my own field: law. Here too, state capacity is mostly notable by its absence. My impression is that the same is true of recently successful libertarian-leaning scholars in economics, philosophy, and political theory, such as John Cochrane, Casey Mulligan, Michael Huemer, and John Tomasi, among others. As David Henderson points out in his response to Tyler, state capacity is also largely absent from the recent research agendas of the most prominent and influential libertarian think tanks and publications, such as the Cato Institute, the Mercatus Center, and Reason.
With the important exception of Tyler himself, I am hard-pressed to name any prominent libertarian thinker who has found success in recent years by focusing on state capacity. The most plausible exception that comes to my mind is Brink Lindsey, who unlike many of his Niskanen Center colleagues, might still be considered a libertarian, at least in some important respects. His excellent and widely discussed 2017 book, The Captured Economy (coauthored with Steve Teles, who is not a libertarian), does indeed advocate a number of state capacity-focused reforms, which are combined with a more traditional libertarian emphasis on deregulation of licensing and zoning (I assessed the book's arguments here and here). I am not at all sure Lindsey would embrace the SCL label. But he may be the closest thing to an example of the phenomenon of "smart" libertarians moving in an SCL direction.
While I follow libertarian intellectual developments closely and know many people in the movement, I have to admit that Tyler knows more. Perhaps he can point to notable examples of libertarian SCL-ers whom I have missed. I would be happy to post any response to my argument that he cares to make. For the moment, however, the available evidence suggests that there is no significant outmigration from libertarianism, and that very few "smart" libertarians are adopting an SCL perspective.
The fact that SCL seems to have very few adherents - even by comparison with conventional libertarianism - doesn't mean SCL is wrong. Many, perhaps most, great ideas start out with very few supporters. In my next post on this issue, I will take up the question of whether libertarians should embrace SCL, regardless of whether any significant number have done so already.
UPDATE: The second post in this series is here.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Women don't like libertarianism because they are the beneficiaries of the Big State. When the State gives you tons of free stuff and preferential treatment you tend to like that not want to limit it.
You may say that you don’t agree with his thesis, but your actual legal reasoning and opinions are in line with his.
Once again, a notable piece discussing the essence of libertarianism which fails even to mention the essence of either its ideological limitations, or its limited appeal.
In a nutshell, the problem is that libertarianism has no theory of sovereignty. That by itself reduces its possibilities to various shades of anarchy. Not many folks trust anarchy.
As constructed by the founders, the American system of government is utterly dependent on the notion of popular sovereignty. Indeed, the most politically acute founders believed, and said, that every nation state must be backed by a sovereign which enjoys unlimited power. During the centuries since the founding, the development of nationalism across the world suggests two important points about that view:
1. It was correct. All modern nation states, without exception, are ultimately ruled by sovereigns of unlimited power.
2. The American system of popular sovereignty—which has been very widely imitated among the more-successful nations—has greatly ameliorated most of the worst defects inherent in the theory of unlimited-power sovereignty.
The theoretical edifice the founders built has endured, and endurance has made it imposing. Most Americans (especially including would-be libertarians), of course, have no notion of these theoretical underpinnings, but they like the result well enough to stand as powerful bloc in favor of the status quo. Flavors of anarchy have no place on their menu.
Thus, until libertarianism develops its own theory of sovereignty, it cannot really be considered a theory of government at all. It's worst contradiction is founded in that insufficiency. Libertarianism posits the most-limited of limited governments—without proposing any power to impose the limitations.
Under the American system as it is, people enjoy rights because they are jointly sovereign, and as the joint sovereign, the People exercise power superior to government. If government abuses their rights, sovereign power, at least in principle, and usually in fact, reins in government. That is the most important fact backing the notion of limited government—that there is actual power to impose the limitations if government gets out of line.
Let libertarians invent something similar, and their political fortunes would improve. Problem is, deep down, inside, libertarians fear and reject that kind of power, so for now they are stuck. They want more rights than anyone else, but they have no notion how to enforce rights against government.
"In a nutshell, the problem is that libertarianism has no theory of sovereignty."
Wrong. Libertarianism has no theory of state sovereignty. This is because it views the individual as the sovereign, not groups. Libertarianism is inherently devoted to methodological individualism in it's approach, because it's focus is on the rights of the individual, the only thing that naturally has any rights.
This has got to be the biggest problem libertarianism has: getting people to stop thinking that government creates society, or is the same, or is required for society to stumble along. It's such an alien concept to me that I don't really understand why people cling to it, but they sure do.
^This * 1000
"This has got to be the biggest problem libertarianism has"
The biggest problem libertarianism has is that no two libertarians agree on much of anything, starting specifically with just what it means to be "libertarian". As a result it's not so much an ideology or a movement, so much as a related set of ideologies or movements.
As a result of THAT, libertarians spend a LOT of time and effort explaining why other libertarians aren't really libertarians, just misguided fools who almost but don't quite get it.
Brett, you just agreed with me. I said libertarianism is not a theory of government, and you are right there saying the same thing.
Your definition of "government" does not include self-government. You are only thinking in statist terms.
Generally agree with this, although for popular sovereignty to have any chance in hell of actually working to rein in government, the governmental powers need to be as decentralized as possible.
A lot of different things seem to get lumped under "libertarian." Most regular people will just see such a label as signifying the general thrust of a person's policy preferences relative to the status quo, rather than a defined set of dogma or an intricately defined philosophy. That's my take anyway. And so having some libertarianish leanings or positions would simply denote the kinds of policy preferences a person would wish to effect by the exercise of popular sovereignty.
To be completely snarky, Libertarianism's biggest problem is that you can't buy enough votes with smaller government
"...you can't buy enough votes with smaller government"
Indeed. Half the country think they're entitled to be taken care of (fed, housed, kept in good health, etc.) by the government. And the other half think it's unfair not to do it! It's a miracle Republicans still win occasionally...
M L, I think you offer a reasonable critique. I largely agree. Of course, that means we both concede that libertarianism is not a theory of government in itself, but only a style of criticism to be directed at governments run on other principles.
" for popular sovereignty to have any chance in hell of actually working to rein in government, the governmental powers need to be as decentralized as possible."
So, your political ideals occur in failed states?
I don't see how "state capacity libertarianism" actually qualifies as a form of libertarianism. As described it seems to be defined in terms of its departures from libertarianism as normally understood, not whatever libertarian elements remain.
"State capacity libertarianism" is an oxymoron, coined by a statist who doesn't want to admit he likes state power.
Exactly correct
Perhaps state capacity libertarianism seems an easier political sell than other varieties. Maybe that's what is "smart" about it.
Some people think they get the greatest liberty when government is prevented from limiting their choices. Some people think they get the greatest liberty when all forces of whatever type are prevented from limiting their choices. People in that latter category count having government keeping other people from limiting their choices as a net positive, even if the other people do not.
Professor Somin,
As this blog is intended for a general audience, perhaps you could start your post could start with a paragraph or maybe just a sentence briefly explaining what “state capacity libertarianism” is. You might give similar definitions for the other kinds of libertarianism.
You don’t have to do this of course. In a scholarly journal it’s normal to assume the readership is familiar with the basic key concepts and terms. And I understand your argument is really intended for scholars, not a general audience. But in writing a post, perhaps it might be best to be a little bit more forgiving of the audience, assume a little less, and explain a little more.
I don't understand the phrase either. I've been reading all the discussions, trying to get some feel for what it means, and cannot get past the impression that it is an oxymoron, that it seems to imply smarter more efficient government rather than less, and that it reminds me of that old founder's saw that if men were angels, we wouldn't need laws, and if angels ran the government, we wouldn't need a Constitution.
If it only means smarter and more efficient government, then Tyler Cowen is even more naive about politics and government than socialists. But I don't really have an answer to your question.
He linked to Tyler's blog post introducing the topic. To a large degree Tyler did a pretty crappy job defining the term which is at least *some* of the problem and why I haven't seen many thinkers jump on board.
I only had to read a couple of paragraphs of Cowen's screed to find that state capacity "libertarianism" means increasing the power of the state, but doing it right. In other words, it's the old fallacy that government would work if we just put the right people in charge - and it's the opposite of "libertarian".
No, that's not the opposite of libertarian. The opposite is authoritarian, or anti-liberty. This is the belief that the less liberty people have, the better, and that any way authority can impose against liberty is better than allowing liberty. It has practically no adherents, but there it is.
Usually impositions on liberty are a byproduct of other goals. Not many people are for constraining liberty with the constraints being an end in itself. But there you have it.
The idea that government would work with the right people in charge is neither pro- nor anti-liberty. What do you want government to do?
Tyler's definition of state capacity libertarianism is not a simple one. But, in so far as it differs from previous versions of libertarianism, largely boils down to a focus on expanding and improving the quality of government, including performing at least some substantial range of functions that most libertarians have traditionally argued should be left to the private sector.
This sounds like a nebulous concept that can be applied by Mr. Cowen in a pinch to paper over some holes, much like Justice Thomas can use "originalism" and his prior lone dissents to achieve a desired outcome.
In all other respects, I join the opinion of Mr. Lathrop in full.
You could have just said "I'm gunna commit the No True Scotsman fallacy now", you know.
That said, have at. In-fighting is funny.
If there's any one reason Libertarians will always be a meme, it's articles like this. The need to label oneself so stringently is ironically not very individualistic and libertarian.
Call it whatever you want, but I think Libertarians are moving towards the realization that you can't be Libertarian and support open borders. More broadly, unlimited freedom. Free movement of people is free movement of ideas and that means demographic erosion and replacement. A Libertarian system that cannot maintain itself is not libertarian. Freedom is not easily acquired, nor is it the natural state of man as freedom is burdensome and requires personal responsibility. Look at how few Americans appreciate and truly defend freedom. Even Libertarians aren't consistent. So it's vitally important that we make sure that any democratic system always has the numbers to protect our rights and, in the event we don't have the numbers, mechanisms to protect freedom even when a plurality or majority opposes it.
I think you've taken the term "smart libertarians" way too literally. I don't think it's meant to be construed as an indication of intelligence. Ever heard a phrase similar to "the smart money has moved out of bonds"? Or, "she wore a smart navy jacket"? In these contexts it means something closer to "trendy" than "intelligent". Granted, Cowen is still wrong since his thesis is nonsensical (Trendy libertarians are statists?) but being overly-literal while fixating on the wrong definition of smart makes this piece read like an intellectual sounding straw man argument. He never asserted that "more intelligent" libertarians had become statists.