The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Washington law bans repeated online posts intended to ‘embarrass' anyone
A Washington state statute criminalizes (among other things) "mak[ing] an electronic communication to … a third party" "with intent to harass, … torment, or embarrass any other person" if the communication is made "[a]nonymously or repeatedly." This deliberately extends beyond unprotected speech (such as true threats or libel). It deliberately extends beyond unwanted speech said to a particular person and forbids embarrassing speech said about that person. Repeatedly criticizing a politician on your blog, for instance, could send you to jail if a prosecutor and judge or jury concludes that you were intending to "harass," "torment" or "embarrass."
I'm delighted to report that leading Internet lawyer Venkat Balasubramani (Focal Law LLC) and I have filed a lawsuit challenging this statute. Our client, Richard Rynearson, actually had a brush with the law as a result of some criticism of a local activist: A police department sent the case to the prosecutor's office, concluding that there was probable cause for the prosecution, and though the prosecutor has not filed charges, he suggested to Rynearson's lawyer that he might file charges based on similar conduct in the future.
I thought I'd post the bulk of our memorandum in support of a preliminary injunction, in case people are interested; it's based on a challenge to a similar Ohio law filed by Ohio lawyer Ray Vasvari and my students Ashford Kneitel, Ryan Nielsen and Elizabeth Sweeney and me several weeks ago. First, a bit about the plaintiff:
Rynearson is an online author and activist who regularly writes online posts and comments to the public related to civil liberties, including about police abuse and the expansion of executive power in the wake of September 11. Rynearson's writings are often critical - and sometimes harshly so - of local public figures and government officials. These writings are in the best traditions of independent American political discourse, and are intended both to raise the awareness of other citizens regarding the civil-liberties issues that Rynearson writes about, and to hold civic and political leaders accountable to the community through pointed criticism. This sort of expression is at the very heart of political speech which the First Amendment most strongly protects.
Many of Rynearson's online posts and comments relate to a detention provision in the National Defense Authorization Act ("NDAA") of 2012, Section 1021, which was found to authorize the unconstitutional detention of American citizens without trial under the laws of war. Given his interest in indefinite-detention issues, Rynearson became interested years ago in public and civic organizations in the Seattle area that memorialize and seek to present the lessons of the Japanese-American internment in World War II, such as the Bainbridge Island Japanese-American Exclusion Memorial and Seattle-based Densho.
In the past months, Rynearson has regularly posted on public Facebook pages and groups criticizing the leadership of those public and civic organizations, because those leaders either failed to condemn the NDAA or vocally and strongly support politicians, such as Governor Jay Inslee and former President Barack Obama, that voted for or signed the NDAA. For example, in February 2017, Rynearson made a series of public posts on Facebook criticizing the founder of the Bainbridge Island Japanese-American Exclusion Memorial ("Memorial") for failing to criticize Governor Inslee and President Obama for voting for/signing the NDAA. The thrust of Rynearson's posts was that the founder should be removed from his role as board member and de facto spokesperson for the Memorial because he used the lessons of the internment, and his role with the Memorial, to criticize Republican politicians (chiefly, President Trump) in many media articles or appearances related to the Memorial, but failed to criticize Democratic politicians.
Rynearson's posts often include invective, ridicule, and harsh language (but no profanity or obscenity) intended to criticize or call into question the actions and motives of these civic leaders and other public figures. He reasonably fears prosecution under the cyberstalking statute for such posts. In fact, the Bainbridge Island Police Department referred a police report to the Kitsap County Prosecutor finding probable cause for cyberstalking based on such critical posts to and about the founder of the Memorial. The prosecutor has not brought charges, but has not officially declined charges either. Instead, the prosecutor plans to revisit his decision regarding charges based on Rynearson's future behavior, including his future speech.
In sum, Rynearson engages in core political expression of a sort squarely within the heartland of what the First Amendment protects, and yet legitimately fears prosecution under the statute based upon the provocative and critical nature of what he writes and publishes online.
And the legal argument:
… A statute is facially invalid under the First Amendment if it is "overbroad," meaning "'a substantial amount of its applications are unconstitutional, judged in relation to [its] plainly legitimate sweep.'" Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is unconstitutionally overbroad on its face, because it criminalizes much heated political and personal commentary of the sort that is routine when people discuss matters that outrage them.
1. Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is an alarmingly broad restriction on pure speech
Section 9.61.260(1)(b) provides that a "person is guilty of cyberstalking if he or she, with intent to harass, intimidate, torment, or embarrass any other person, … makes an electronic communication to such other person or a third party … [a]nonymously or repeatedly whether or not conversation occurs." An "electronic communication" is the "transmission of information by wire, radio, optical cable, electromagnetic, or other similar means … includ[ing], but … not limited to, … internet-based communications." RCW § 9.61.260(5). The statute separately criminalizes electronic speech that contains "any lewd, lascivious, indecent, or obscene words, images, or language," id. § 9.61.260(1)(a), or that "[t]hreaten[s] to inflict injury on the person or property of the person called or any member of his or her family or household," id. § 9.61.260(1)(c). Accordingly, Section 9.61.260(1)(b) criminalizes a vast range of non-obscene, non-threatening speech, based only on (1) purportedly bad intent and (2) repetition or anonymity.
The breadth of the statute extends in several dimensions. First, the intent provision - sweeping in speech that a jury might find was intended to "harass, intimidate, torment, or embarrass any other person" - reaches broadly. The terms "harass, intimidate, torment, or embarrass" are not defined by the statute. The Washington Supreme Court, in a case examining the similarly-worded telephone-harassment statute, has defined "intimidate" to include "compel[ling] to action or inaction (as by threats)," Seattle v. Huff, 767 P.2d 572, 576 (Wash. 1989), but it did not provide a definition for the other proscribed purposes.
When statutory terms are undefined, however, Washington courts generally give them their ordinary meaning, including the dictionary definition. See id. (defining "intimidate" by reference to definition in Webster's Third New International Dictionary). The dictionary definition of "harass" includes "to vex, trouble, or annoy continually or chronically," Webster's Third New International Dictionary, Unabridged (online ed. 2017), and the meaning of "torment" includes "to cause worry or vexation to," id. Finally, "embarrass" means "to cause to experience a state of self-conscious distress." Id. As a result, even public criticisms of public figures and public officials could be subject to criminal prosecution and punishment if they are seen as intended to persistently "vex" or "annoy" those public figures, or to embarrass or make them "self-conscious" about something.
Second, Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is not limited to true threats, obscenity, defamation, or any other category of unprotected speech. In fact, because paragraphs (1)(a) and (1)(c) plainly cover obscenity and threats, respectively, much of the speech that can be restricted due to content under the First Amendment is plainly excluded from Section 9.61.260(1)(b)'s reach, meaning that most of the speech that falls within Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is protected speech.
And even paragraph (1)(a) - which covers "any lewd, lascivious, [or] indecent … words, images, or language" in addition to "obscene" speech - reaches mostly protected speech, i.e., speech that would not fall within the definition of unprotected "obscenity." That paragraph is not directly at issue here, but it illustrates the extreme breadth of the cyberstalking statute and how it reaches core political speech to the public that is protected by the First Amendment. In 2011, for example, the Renton Police Department obtained a search warrant to compel Google to identify the individual who had anonymously posted cartoon videos on YouTube making fun of, and criticizing, the City of Renton and its Police Department. Jennifer Sullivan, Web cartoons making fun of Renton taken seriously, Seattle Times, Aug. 4, 2011. The videos communicated criticisms related to a new jail, internal investigations, and department morale, but also referred to alleged sex acts involving Police Department employees. Id. The police obtained a warrant by contending that the videos were "cyberstalking" due to "lewd content" or "indecent language that is meant to embarrass and emotionally torment" the police officers who were the subjects of the criticism. The same content could just have easily been charged as repeated or anonymous under paragraph (1)(b), because more than one video was posted and the poster used a pen name. The police later dropped the case, but it is nonetheless a useful exemplar of how far the statute reaches.
Third, Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is not confined to harassing speech directed to an unwilling listener. Rather, it expressly covers online speech with intent to embarrass any other person both when spoken to "such person" and to "a third party." Traditionally, criminal harassment laws covered speech said to a particular unwilling person - for instance, telephone calls, letters sent to a particular home, or e-mails sent to a particular person. Thus, for instance, the Supreme Court upheld a federal law forbidding people from sending certain material to others once the recipients have told senders to stop. Rowan v. U.S. Post Office Dep't, 397 U.S. 728, 730 (1970). "[N]o one has a right to press even 'good' ideas on an unwilling recipient," the Court reasoned. Rowan, 397 U.S. at 738. For that reason, Washington may constitutionally be permitted to bar unwanted e-mails after the recipient has told the speaker to stop, as it has done with unwanted telephone calls. RCW § 9.61.230.
But Section 9.61.260(1)(b) goes much further, by criminalizing even public commentary about people. While "attempting to stop the flow of information into [one's] own household" (speech to a person) is constitutional, trying to block criticism of a person said "to the public" (speech about a person) violates the First Amendment. Organization for a Better Austin v. Keefe, 402 U.S. 415, 420 (1971); see also Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 486 (1988) (upholding ban on targeted residential picketing, because such picketing "is narrowly directed at the household, not the public," and is thus "fundamentally different from more generally directed means of communication that may not be completely banned").
And this makes sense: Restrictions on speech to a person (such as unwanted telephone calls) nonetheless allow for dissemination of information to willing listeners. Restrictions on speech about a person are far broader, and thus unconstitutionally undermine "robust political debate" (as well as conversation on other topics). Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 51 (1988).
Finally, because it criminalizes public speech about a person with certain intent, Section 9.61.260(1)(b) regulates pure speech, without any associated noncommunicative conduct. With respect to prohibitions on speech directed to a person, for example with telephone harassment, it is the harassing conduct that is prohibited - i.e., the unwelcome ringing of the telephone, which can awaken or distract people regardless of the message conveyed. The conduct of publicly posting something (independent of the post's content) cannot itself be harassing, intimidating, or embarrassing. Rather, a person can be convicted of cyberstalking based only on the content of his pure speech, without any associated harassing conduct. This distinguishes the Washington cyberstalking statute from other cyberstalking statutes that have been upheld against facial challenges. See United States v. Osinger, 753 F.3d 939, 944 (9th Cir. 2014) (holding that "because 18 U.S.C. § 2261A proscribes harassing and intimidating conduct, the statute is not facially invalid under the First Amendment," as the "proscribed acts are tethered to the underlying criminal conduct and not to speech"); id. at 954 (Watford, J., concurring) ("If a defendant is doing nothing but exercising a right of free speech, without engaging in any non-speech conduct, the exception for speech integral to criminal conduct shouldn't apply.").
Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is thus "a criminal prohibition of alarming breadth." Stevens, 130 S. Ct. at 1588. It potentially punishes a vast range of harsh rhetoric about political candidates. Even Hillary Clinton and Donald Trump could have been punished under this statute, if they had Tweeted things in Washington that were intended to "harass" or "embarrass" each other. The statute also punishes a vast range of criticism of local civic and political leaders on matters of local or national public concern, because any harsh or repeated critique could be perceived as being done with intent to harass or embarrass.
Beyond that, the statute punishes much speech that is part of everyday life. Say, for instance, that a woman breaks up with her unfaithful boyfriend, and she posts on her Facebook page about how she feels about him. A prosecutor may easily conclude that the woman posted her Facebook message with the "intent to harass … or embarrass" her ex-boyfriend, by making him feel ashamed. Yet such speech on the details of our daily lives is also constitutionally protected. Even "[w]holly neutral futilities" that lack political, artistic, or similar value are "still sheltered from government regulation."
2. Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is not saved by the requirement of bad purpose
Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is not rendered constitutional by the requirement that the speech be intended to harass, torment, intimidate, or embarrass. The Supreme Court has repeatedly held that bad intentions do not strip speech of constitutional protection. Thus, in Garrison v. Louisiana, the Court rejected the view that reputation-injuring speech could be punished because of the speaker's allegedly bad motives, such as a "wanton desire to injure." 379 U.S. 64, 78 (1964). As the Court explained, "[i]f upon a lawful occasion for making a publication, [a speaker] has published the truth, and no more, there is no sound principle which can make him liable, even if he was actuated by express malice." Id. at 73 (internal quotation marks and citation omitted).
Likewise, in Hustler Magazine, the Supreme Court overturned an intentional infliction of emotional distress verdict, concluding that a bad motive does not strip speech of constitutional protection. 485 U.S. at 53. And in Snyder v. Phelps, the Court applied this principle to speech about private figures as well as public figures. 562 U.S. 443, 458 (2011). More broadly, the Supreme Court has held that a "speaker's motivation" is generally "entirely irrelevant to the question of constitutional protection." FEC v. Wis. Right to Life, Inc., 551 U.S. 449, 468 (2007) (citation omitted); id. at 495 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment) (likewise rejecting a test based on speaker motivation). This Court has likewise held a speech restriction unconstitutional notwithstanding the inclusion of an intent requirement that prohibited publication of certain information "with the intent to harm or intimidate." Sheehan v. Gregoire, 272 F. Supp. 2d 1135, 1149 (W.D. Wash. 2003) ("[T]he First and Fourteenth Amendments preclude the State of Washington from proscribing pure speech based solely on the speaker's subjective intent.") (holding that statute prohibiting publication of, among other things, the residential address and phone numbers of law enforcement officials with "intent to harm or intimidate" was facially unconstitutional because it was overbroad).
The Supreme Court has offered two reasons for this protection of speech without regard to purpose. First, speech remains valuable even if its motives may be unsavory. "[E]ven if [a speaker] did speak out of hatred, utterances honestly believed contribute to the free interchange of ideas and the ascertainment of truth." Garrison, 379 U.S. at 73.
Second, restricting speech based on its bad motive risks chilling even well-motivated speech. "Debate on public issues will not be uninhibited if the speaker must run the risk that it will be proved in court that he spoke out of hatred … ." Id. "No reasonable speaker would choose to run an ad covered by [the statute] if its only defense to a criminal prosecution would be that its motives were pure. An intent-based standard blankets with uncertainty whatever may be said, and offers no security for free discussion." Wis. Right to Life, 551 U.S. at 468 (Roberts, C.J., joined by Alito, J.) (internal quotation marks omitted). "First Amendment freedoms need breathing space to survive," and "[a]n intent test provides none." Id. at 468-69 (citations omitted). Any effort to distinguish restricted speech from unrestricted speech "based on intent of the speaker would 'offe[r] no security for free discussion,' and would 'compe[l] the speaker to hedge and trim.'" Id. at 495 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment, joined by Kennedy and Thomas, JJ.) (internal citations and some internal quotation marks omitted).
The same applies to Section 9.61.260(1)(b). Rynearson, and others like him, will constantly have to worry that their harsh criticism of public figures or public officials might be seen as ill-motivated by a prosecutor, and might put them at risk of jail. Section 9.61.260(1)(b) "offe[rs] no security for free discussion," and "provides no[]" "breathing space" for speech; it is therefore unconstitutional.
3. Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is not saved by the requirement of repetition or anonymity
Other than intent, the only requirement for speech to be criminalized by Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is that it be repeated or anonymous. The anonymity element only renders the prohibition more unconstitutional, not less. An "'author's decision to remain anonymous, like other decisions concerning omissions or additions to the content of a publication, is an aspect of the freedom of speech protected by the First Amendment.'" Doe, 772 F.3d at 574 (quoting McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Comm'n, 514 U.S. 334, 342 (1995)). Anonymity on the internet is no less protected, because "online speech stands on the same footing as other speech." Id. (citation omitted). Indeed, the Supreme Court has recently recognized "the most important place[] (in a spatial sense) for the exchange of views … is cyberspace - the vast democratic forums of the Internet in general, and social media in particular." Packingham v. North Carolina, 137 S. Ct. 1730, 1735 (2017).
And the repetition element does not save the statute, either. Speech does not lose its protection because it is said more than once. The individuals distributing leaflets in Organization for a Better Austin distributed at least four different leaflets targeting a realtor and criticizing his business practices, and they distributed leaflets for "several days" at a shopping center, on "two other occasions" at the realtor's church, and at least one other time, at the houses of the realtor's neighbors. 402 U.S. at 417. That is surely "repeated" speech targeting a particular individual, but the Supreme Court nonetheless held it was protected by the First Amendment, even though it was "intended to exercise a coercive impact on" the realtor. Id. at 419.
4. Section 9.61.260(1)(b) restricts protected speech based on its content, and must therefore be judged under strict scrutiny (which it cannot pass)
The government generally "has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content." Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2226 (2015) (citation omitted). Defining "regulated speech by its function or purpose" makes a restriction "content based." And that is precisely what Section 9.61.260(1)(b) does - it criminalizes speech based on the speaker's purpose, i.e. intent. Moreover, a law is content-based when, "[i]n order to enforce the regulation, an official must necessarily examine the content of the message that is conveyed." ACLU of Nev. v. City of Las Vegas, 466 F.3d 784, 794 (9th Cir. 2006); see also Sheehan, 272 F. Supp. 2d at 1146 ("When an individual enforcing a statute must examine the content of the speech to determine whether the statute governs, the statute is content-based."). Determining whether online speech about someone (but not delivered to that person) was intended to harass or embarrass will necessarily require examination of the speech's content.
Nor can the restriction be treated as content-neutral under the so-called "secondary effects" doctrine, under which the government can adopt a "time, place, or manner regulation aimed at the 'secondary effects' of the proscribed speech." Sheehan, 272 F. Supp. 2d at 1146. "The emotive impact of speech on its audience is not a 'secondary effect'"; laws that "regulate[] speech due to its potential primary impact" - such as their emotive impact on the targets of the speech - "must be considered content-based." Boos v. Barry, 485 U.S. 312, 321 (1988) (lead opinion); id. at 334 (Brennan, J., concurring in the judgment). See also Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 412 (1989) ("[T]he emotive impact of speech on its audience is not a 'secondary effect' unrelated to the content of the expression itself.") (internal quotation marks omitted); Sheehan, 272 F. Supp. 2d at 1146. Likewise, Section 9.61.260(1)(b), which aims to control the emotional impact of speech by banning speech intended to "harass, torment, intimidate, or embarrass," is therefore content-based.
Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is thus subject to strict scrutiny, and is therefore "presumptively unconstitutional" unless it "furthers a compelling interest and is narrowly tailored to achieve that interest." Moreover, because Rynearson has made a "colorable claim that [his] First Amendment rights have been infringed, or are threatened with infringement," it is Defendants' burden "to justify the restriction." Defendants cannot meet that burden. There is no compelling state interest in forbidding all non-threatening and non-obscene online speech that is seen as having a caustic purpose.
Moreover, Section 9.61.260(1)(b) is far from "narrowly tailored." To be narrowly tailored, a content-based restriction on speech must be "the least restrictive means of furthering a compelling government interest." Yet Section 9.61.260(1)(b) restricts a broad range of speech that falls far outside any First Amendment exception - indeed, it mostly restricts such speech because it excludes speech that could be considered to fall within the unprotected categories of obscenity and true threats. Moreover, Section 9.61.260(1)(b) does not require that the subject of the offending speech suffer any legally cognizable injury, or even be aware of the speech. See State v. Bishop, 787 S.E.2d 814, 820 (N.C. 2016) (reasoning that an anti-cyberbullying statute did not satisfy strict scrutiny, in part, because the statute did not require that the victim suffer an injury or even know about the offending speech). It is the antithesis of a narrowly-tailored restriction.
Show Comments (0)