The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
How Would You Know If a Justice Issues A Wise, Solomonic Ruling?
Here's looking at you, Chief.
The Free Press published an extended excerpt from Justice Barrett's new book. Justice Barrett develops at some length the theme of King Solomon. She reminds readers that Solomon never actually cut the baby in half. Rather, his wisdom was putting forward a test that would identify the real mother, without having to murder the child. And that test has endured for milennia. Barrett writes:
"Doing justice" doesn't call to mind a judge parsing statutory language; it sounds more like King Solomon, who famously mediated the dispute between two women claiming the same baby. In a brilliant (if high risk) strategy, Solomon proposed to divide the baby in half, betting that the true mother would relinquish the child rather than see him die.
Fortunately, Solomon was right. And because he achieved the just result, the Old Testament memorializes this story to illustrate Solomon's wisdom. In fact, Solomon is also honored on a frieze in the courtroom of the Supreme Court, where he appears as one of the "great lawgivers of history."
Barrett goes on to say that King Solomon is not the right model for a federal judge. Federal judges do not decide cases based on internal wisdom, but they decide cases based on external law.
It's notable to me that Solomon's wisdom came from within. He didn't resolve the case by turning to sources like laws passed by a legislature or precedents set by other judges. Nor was there any limit to the kind of solution he could impose—after all, his proposed remedy was to literally split the baby. Solomon's authority was bounded by nothing more than his own judgment. But that wasn't cause for concern, because the man and wise rule were one and the same.
If you'd asked me before law school, I may well have identified Solomon as the ideal judge. And in a certain respect, he is—it's appealing to entrust a dispute to someone who resolves it with reference solely to principles of justice. Solomon, however, stands out for a reason: His wisdom was flawless. Those who framed and ratified the Constitution didn't expect the same to be true of federal judges.
Barrett is exactly right here. Indeed, I have difficulty with the fact that the slogan chiseled into stone atop the Supreme Court is "Equal Justice Under Law." That phrase has no home in any legal authority. It was proposed by the architects of the Supreme Court. I suppose it is technically correct that the justice must be done under some type of written law, but that phrase conveys all the wrong message to litigants. The job of a judge is not to dispense justice, as she sees it.
Justice Barrett's point brings to mind a rather infamous statement made repeatedly by then-Judge Sonia Sotomayor. She would often say that a "wise Latina woman with the richness of her experience would more often than not reach a better conclusion than a white male who hasn't lived that life." King Solomon could perhaps draw on his wisdom, but federal judges should not. Then again, Justice Ketanji Brown Jackson recently described "equal justice under law" as "this Court's guiding light nearly a century after those words were first engraved there." Not quite.
Barrett continues to develop the Solomon theme with regard to the death penalty. She restates her longstanding moral opposition to capital punishment. Yet, she still voted to affirm the death sentence for the Boston Marathon bomber. Barrett peels back the curtain a bit and explains how she could have issued a Solomonic vote, in which her legal judgment was (quietly) informed by her moral beliefs. Barrett writes that no one would have ever known if she had done this--not even her colleagues. (Does Barrett think that some judges do this?) But Barrett saw such an action as a dereliction of her duty, and violation of her oath. Read these passages carefully:
Soon after my appointment, the Court considered a death sentence imposed on Dzhokhar Tsarnaev, one of the Boston Marathon bombers. The court of appeals had vacated Tsarnaev's sentence, and the United States argued that it had done so in error. I thought that the United States was right, and I joined the Court's holding that Tsarnaev's death sentence was valid.
That was not the only course open to me. Given my view of capital punishment, I could have looked for ways to slant the law in favor of defendants facing the death penalty. There were, after all, plausible arguments going Tsarnaev's way—the court of appeals agreed with him, as did three of my colleagues in dissent. Had I voted in favor of Tsarnaev, no one would have known that I did it because I objected to the death penalty rather than because I concluded that Tsarnaev had the better of the argument.
But that would have been a dereliction of duty. The people who adopted the Constitution didn't share my view of the death penalty, and neither do all my fellow citizens today. Quite the contrary: 27 states authorize capital punishment, as does the federal government.
If I distort the law to make it difficult for them to impose the death penalty, I interfere with the voters' right to self-government. My office doesn't entitle me to align the legal system with my moral or policy views. Swearing to apply the law faithfully means deciding each case based on my best judgment about what the law is, not what it should be.
I found the vote distasteful to cast, and I wish our system worked differently. Yet I had no doubt that voting to affirm the sentence was the right thing for me to do. Had I concluded that casting such a vote was immoral or that I couldn't fairly judge the case, the right thing to do would have been to recuse—not to cheat.
Once again, Barrett's prose brings to mind another one of her colleagues. Who on the Supreme Court is known to "distort" the law to reach "Solomonic" rulings based on a broader sense of "Justice"? Hmmm…..
Let me quote a law professor from 2017, writing about NFIB v. Sebelius:
In NFIB v. Sebelius, the inspiration for Barnett's book, Chief Justice Roberts pushed the Affordable Care Act beyond its plausible meaning to save the statute. He construed the penalty imposed on those without health insurance as a tax, which permitted him to sustain the statute as a valid exercise of the taxing power; had he treated the payment as the statute did—as a penalty—he would have had to invalidate the statute as lying beyond Congress's commerce power.
That law professor, of course, was Amy Coney Barrett, writing a review of Randy Barnett's book. On this front, I agree with Professor Barrett. Here is how I described Chief Justice Roberts's tenure of "faux-Solomonic" rulings:
Roberts's defining rulings are not models of judicial excellence. Instead, they dole benefits to the left and the right in a transparent effort to split the baby. In NFIB v. Sebelius (2012), Robert changed his vote to uphold the Affordable Care Act. But to reach that result, Roberts rewrote a penalty into a tax, and rewrote the mandatory Medicaid expansion into an optional program. And he did so during an apparently successful pressure campaign from legal elites. Few people believe that Roberts offered the best reading on the law based on neutral principles. Rather, the Chief twisted and turned the law to avoid striking down President Obama's signature law, while still preserving some conservative separation of powers principles. More than a decade later, we are stuck not with the healthcare law that Congress adopted, but with the compromise that Chief Justice Roberts brokered.
During the first Trump Administration, Roberts issued a troika of split rulings. First, in Department of Commerce v. New York (2019), Robert ruled that the executive branch had the broad power to inquire about citizenship status on the census. But, Roberts parried, the Trump Administration's reasons for adding the question was "pretextual," and further proceedings were needed to consider the rationale. Professor Noah Feldman of Harvard observed, "Roberts's approach . . . is to try to craft a middle ground that will make the Supreme Court seem less purely political than it would if he opted to join the conservatives."
Second, in Department of Homeland Security v. Regents of the University of California (2020), Roberts ruled that the executive branch could in theory terminate the DACA immigration policy. But in this case, the Trump Administration failed to adequately consider how that termination would affect the Dreamers. Again, a victory for the presidency, but a loss for Trump. Joan Biskupic of CNN lauded Roberts's decision as "pragmatic and political."
The third case, June Medical LLC v. Russo (2020), involved abortion. Four years earlier, Roberts dissented in a 5-4 decision that halted abortion restrictions from Texas. But in June Medical, Roberts could have been the fifth vote to pare back Roe v. Wade. Instead, Roberts declared unconstitutional abortion restrictions from Louisiana that were nearly indistinguishable from the Texas abortion restrictions that he had favored. An anonymous conservative writer told Vox, "The only way to make sense of the Supreme Court's abortion jurisprudence is to assume it is guided by one principle: 'Pro-lifers must lose.'"
Roberts's triangulations continued during the Biden Administration. In Dobbs v. Jackson Women's Health Organization (2022), the Supreme Court at long last overruled Roe v. Wade. Chief Justice Roberts did not join the majority opinion. Nor did he join the dissenters, and vote to reaffirm the Court's abortion precedents. Rather, the Chief Justice split the difference again. Roberts ruled that Mississippi's fifteen week abortion ban was permissible because pregnant women still had a "reasonable" opportunity to have an abortion. According to press reports, Roberts was attempting to persuade Justices Kavanaugh or Barrett to join his opinion, thus fragmenting the majority opinion. Thankfully, his efforts failed. Where did this manufactured rule come from? Who knows. Justice Alito explained that Roberts lacked "any principled basis," and "would do exactly what [he] criticizes Roe for doing: pulling 'out of thin air' a test that "[n]o party or amicus asked the Court to adopt." Here, Roberts wove a new standard out of whole cloth, but this Emperor had no clothes. . . .
Roberts's decisions are often described as "Solomonic," but this label disregards the wisdom of the biblical monarch. King Solomon never actually cut the baby in half, but developed a test to resolve the dispute: the real mother could not bear to see her child harmed. This timeless principle is still taught today. But Roberts's opinions are tickets good for one ride, if that. They do not extend beyond the narrow confines of the decision. Roberts cannot lay claim to King Solomon's throne.
I found myself nodding while reading Barrett's excerpt. Indeed, I reached very much the same conclusion about Solomon and judging. Yet, I take the extra step and apply that scrutiny to the current members of the Court. And Chief Justice Roberts fits the bill.
Now I appreciate that Justice Barrett writes that she does not issue Solomonic rulings that split the baby. Yet, many of her decisions sure do feel that way, especially when she is the fifth vote. Most recently, she split the difference in NIH v. APHA--counts about cutting funding belong in the Court of Federal Claims, but APA challenges can remain in District Court. In Department of State v. AIDS Vaccine Advocacy Coalition, Barrett declined to enjoin the lower court, yet still hinted that the lower court should reduce the amount of money that has to be spent. In Trump v. United States, Barrett generally found presidential immunity, but would have let certain evidentiary issues be settled at trial. In Trump v. Anderson, well, I'm still not entirely sure what her position was, but it was somewhere in the middle. In South Bay United Pentecostal Church v. Newsom, Barrett's first-ever opinion, she held that California could not shut down churches, but they could ban singing. I could go on. There does seem to be a lot of baby-splitting going on--but nowhere near as much as the Chief.
I think this post illustrates my difficulty with Justice Barrett, and why people don't quite get my criticism of her. I usually agree with Justice Barrett on first principles. I then struggle with how she follows through to apply those principles. To use a gymnastic analogy, Barrett scores high on the difficulty score, but is weaker on her execution score. She sets out up do something extremely important, and only sometimes reaches that level. CASA, PennEast, and a couple other cases are healthy exceptions to the rule. She needs to consistently stick the landing.
Moreover, as I've written before, I don't know if Justice Barrett always sees the consequences of her decisions, and how it affects other facets of what she has done. This excerpt should make any informed reader think of Chief Justice Roberts or Justice Sotomayor. I am confident this was not intentional, but it is there. By describing what she does not do as bad, she is judging those who do the opposite of Barrett.
I will read Justice Barrett's book with an open mind. The short excerpts I've seen so far are well-written, cogent, and bring some insights into her decision-making process. Query how much of this she could have described in a book proposal from 2021 when she struck the book deal.
One final note. Isn't Marbury the ultimate Solomonic ruling? Chief Justice Marshall ruled that Madison violated the law, but declined to grant the writ. Even if Marbury can be defended as a plausible reading of Article III and the Judiciary Act of 1789, I think most scholars see the decision as a strategic jujitsu from the wise Chief Justice. This is not behavior that should be emulated. If I ever become Chief Justice for a day (Lord help us all) I would sandblast the phrase "Equal Justice Under Law" off the west pediment and send the larger-than-life John Marshall statute down to Richmond. Each Justice should have a bust or statute or portrait of (roughly) the same size. It is wrong to elevate one member above all others.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
I'm not overconvinced by this line of argument. The question of how judges should behave is (a) whether the judge should stick anally to the rule that he has been presented with, and come up with a ruling that applies the facts to the rule as robotically as possible; or (b) whether he should survey the rights and wrongs as he sees it, and give the cookie to the most deserving.
The former is my opinion, the latter is your basic sarcasuistry.
But the point of the Solomon story is that he was using a trick to discover the true facts. There was no question about what the law was - the baby should go to its mother. These days it's the attorneys, not the judges, who get to deploy such tricks - in the form of questions - to get their opponents, or witnesses, to make admissions against their interests. Nothing wrong with that.
The story has always been odd to me. So the woman who was not the mother and trying to kidnap the child would have been just fine with half of a bloody and mangled baby corpse? Just walked away with her compromise victory?
Yeah, it doesn’t make any sense. And like, were there not any witnesses to who the real mother was? Like maybe that would have been a better way to resolve the issue? “Yeah, that’s Martha from my village. She was definitely pregnant and has been nursing her baby every time I see her. Don’t know who this other chick is. Never seen her around before.”
The other woman had been pregnant too, and in the same house. Her baby died. She then stole the live child.
In Denner's Wreck by Lawrence Watt-Evans, one of the technologically advanced space travelers who are worshiped as gods by a primitive colony attempts Solomon's trick but is disappointed when both women are equally horrified. So he does genetic testing to determine which is the mother, finds the dead infant's body and clones it.
It makes perfect sense, as Lee and Bubba explained below.
Today, some people would make everyone objectively poorer with economic policy, rather than suffer wealth inequality.
Another example story. A client once told an attorney they would rather see their parents' entire estate exhausted by attorney fees than see the other heirs getting anything.
Yes, but the woman hadn't "lost" yet however she readily agreed to the proposal. Why not, "No, please don't do that!"?
She was just like, "Meh, sounds fair."
The woman who stole the baby had lost her own, so she might have been quite content that the other mother should lose hers.
Envy is the desire that another should be deprived of the thing that they have, not the desire that you should have it for yourself (that is covertousness.)
Bingo. She was angry that the other woman had something she could not.
"If I can't have it, no one can" is a pretty common human feeling.
Parents, on the other hand, are expected to do what's best for the child, even if it's not what they themselves want or need.
It fascinates me that at least two people in this thread don't grok that.
There have been several proposals on how this problem can be addressed:
- it's not who the biological mother is, but who should be given custody, given the best interest of the child. Woman 2, the one who is fine with the bloody corpse, may well have been the biological mother, maybe suffering from post-natal depression, insanity or some other reason that makes her unfit to be given custody of the child. Woman 1 displays by contrast she cares genuinely for the child, and should therefore be declared, in law, to be its "mother"
- Salomon was a bit of an idiot. In this analysis, he strictly applied the entirely wrong rule. In rabbinic law, if two people contest ownership of a piece of cloth by both holding on to it, the dispute is solved by cutting it in half ( Emanuel Quint (1998) A Restatement of Rabbinic Civil Law) Salomon did not get that this is not a good rule to apply to babies. The court was shocked, but the court scribe was gently nudged by the guards (who had really big clubs) to make it sound like a wise decision. The inconsistencies that resulted are inevitable
- the 3. is complicated (proposed by Baruch C. Cohen (1998) The Brilliant Wisdom of King Solomon, Jewish Law) If you look at the way the story is reported, Woman 1, the real mother, immediately concedes. At this point under rabbinic procedural law, Woman 2 had already won, she could simply have said nothing and walked away with the child. Instead, she then, and only then, suggests the cutting. Now, to make sense of this and your point, Cohen remarks that both women represented themselves, not through any male guardians, which means that they were widows. As they were not accused of infidelity, the child must have been their deceased husband's. Under Yibbum law, a childless widow must marry the husband's brother. So woman 2 only wants the child to avoid having to remarry. A dead child does the job just as well (provided it is older than 30 days) For her, it has the added advantage not to have to look after someone else's child.
This and some other interpretations that have been suggested are discussed in Schafer,B. . "The courtroom as laboratory. in Z. Bankowski (ed) The Universal and the Particular in Legal Reasoning (2006)
This post puts a lot of weight on analogies with Solomon threatening to split a baby, but actually splitting the difference on a policy question is fundamentally not analogous to what Solomon did: Not only can public policy survive such a decision, one could argue that public policy is improved by the bisection (... and a judge who rules that way usually makes such an argument, either explicitly or implicitly).
All the verbal effluence does not answer the question posed in the title, because it fails to identify judicial decisions that can be assessed as Solomonic or not.
I routinely disagree with MP, but he is correct here. The entire metaphor here is inapplicable. A baby is inherently unitary; either it belonged to one mother or the other. So the proposed resolution by Solomon was definitely wrong and was used only to identify the true mother.
But there's no reason any of the cases that Blackman is kvetching about had to be resolved entirely one way or the other. It could be entirely correct that one provision of a law is constitutional and a different provision is unconstitutional. Or that a particular policy could be legal if enacted one way but not legal if enacted another way.
In most policy litigation, it doesn't really matter how the judge rules. If congress doesn't like the outcome, they can change or clarify the policy.
The parties would obviously disagree.
Yes.. basically what I posted below. As Barrett explained the original split the baby had nothing to do with splitting the difference.
There is an alternative, minority, view of the story of Solomon.
It holds that Solomon knew who the real mother was all along. Rather than simply explaining this and awarding the baby to the rightful mother, he deployed his trick.
Why?
Solomon was only one of many sons of David, and not the eldest by any means. His legitimacy was in question, and he was in some danger from other sons and their supporters. By pulling off this maneuver, which would have made him look very bad had it failed he established his reputation for great wisdom, and enhanced his legitimacy as king.
Indeed, 1 Kings, Chapter 3, concludes with:
And all Israel heard of the judgment which the king had judged; and they feared the king; for they saw that the wisdom of God was in him, to do justice.
So Solomon acted very wisely, indeed, but the object of the behavior may not be what we think.
I have difficulty with the fact that the slogan chiseled into stone atop the Supreme Court is "Equal Justice Under Law." That phrase has no home in any legal authority. ....
The job of a judge is not to dispense justice, as she sees it.
No, but neither the slogan nor Jackson are suggesting that. There is no implied argument that it is solely up to the judge's personal views.
It calls for equal justice under the law. IOW, look to the law, and apply it equally.
Nice try.
Today we happily kill babies every day.
And no one gets punished.
I am genuinely glad that intellectual heavyweight Bari Weiss's blog and the genius of Amy Coney Barrett helped you understand the Judgment of Solomon, since you have _frequently_ used it incorrectly as a metaphor in your posts and you don't read comments to see any of the times you're corrected on it.
I find this behavior hilarious.
Dude is perpetually online, devolving into a political hack, and completely insulated from any reactions.
He's like any other social media princess who doesn't care how you react, so long as you react.
Blackman's position is how you end up executing innocent people. It is, therefore, wrong.
Don’t really see the problem with equal justice under law. Judges are supposed to apply the law equally to all people and thereby do justice. If the law favors some people over others, that doesn’t mean it’s being unequally applied. It just means the law, in that instance, favors them for some reason.
So if the law punishes juveniles less harshly than adults, all juveniles have that benefit. But between juveniles, the law should be equally applied as the law dictates. A judge who gave special privileges to some juveniles and not others in like circumstances wouldn’t be doing justice.
Likewise if the law required the same punishment for like-situated juveniles and adults. If the judge decided that juveniles should get a special break because they’re juveniles, that too wouldn’t be doing justice.
Notice, though, that equal justice under law applies to courts not legislatures. Except when a higher law—e.g., a constitution—requires equal treatment, a lawmaker can discriminate between people because they determine what the law is. Judges, however, merely apply the law to discrete litigants, and must therefore do so equally as the law requires. No favoritism is allowed in the latter as it (generally) is in the former.
To say that "Equal Justice Under Law" is a mere "phrase" that "has no home in any legal authority" betrays a level of ignorance of our Constitution and federal law that is astounding of someone who purports to teach our Constitution.
Justice is emphatically required repeatedly in the supreme law of the land. The Preamble (which established the sovereignty of the people) emphasized that "We the People" did "ordain and establish" our "Constitution" precisely to "establish Justice" and "secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves." Whether a bigot personally likes that principle or not is irrelevant.
Amendment V expressly provided that “No person” (citizen or not) can be “deprived of life” or any “liberty” or any “property” until after being afforded all “process of law” that is “due.” Due process of law clearly necessarily implies and requires equal protection of the laws. Chief Justice John Marshall writing for SCOTUS emphasized that precise point in one of SCOTUS’s earliest and most famous decisions, Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803). “The very essence of civil liberty certainly consists in the right of every individual to claim the protection of the laws, whenever he receives an injury. One of the first duties of government is to afford that protection.”
Amendment XIV says as much especially clearly regarding state and local governments. “No State” has any power to “make or enforce any law” that “abridge[s any] privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States.” “No State” has any power to “deprive any person” (citizen or not) “of life” or any “liberty” or any “property” until after affording them all “process of law” that is “due.” “No State” has any power to “deny to any person” (citizen or not) “the equal protection of the laws.”
Every federal judge or justice must and does promise (under 28 U.S.C. 453) to "administer justice without respect to persons, and do equal right to the poor and to the rich, and" to "faithfully and impartially discharge and perform all the duties [ ] under the Constitution and laws of the United States."
If Blackman is teaching what he preached in this piece, he is not supporting our Constitution. He is flouting it.
With this piece, Blackman betrays his profoundly anti-constitutional attitude toward our Constitution. He reveals his personal opposition to the plain meaning of the plain text of our Constitution. He represents that he "usually agree[s] with Justice Barrett on first principles." But Blackman made clear that he does not agree with our Constitution regarding its first principles.
Americans should beware of the degeneracy of people like Blackman. As Madison reminded Americans in the Virginia Report of 1800:
"[A] frequent recurrence to fundamental principles [in our constitutions] is solemnly enjoined by most of the state constitutions, and particularly by our own [Constitution], as a necessary safeguard against the danger of degeneracy to which republics are liable . . . . The authority of constitutions over governments, and of the sovereignty of the people over constitutions, are truths which are at all times necessary to be kept in mind; and at no time perhaps more necessary than at the present."
We the People do not exist to give certain people power. We put people in power to solely to represent us solely to accomplish the purposes stated in the Preamble. And as Article VI emphasized, our "Constitution" is first and foremost among "the supreme Law of the Land" and all state and federal legislators and "all executive and judicial Officers" are "bound" to "support our "Constitution" without being guided by any "religious" viewpoint.
Blackman's religious views should be irrelevant to him when he purports to teach our Constitution, and his religious views are irrelevant to all legitimate analysis of the extent to which judicial decisions and opinions actually do fulfill the oaths of judges and actually do support and defend our Constitution.
Blackman's support for the majority opinion in Dobbs further reveals Blackman's own profound lack of integrity and lack of commitment to supporting our Constitution. That opinion was founded on a lie about, and a knowingly violation of, the plain meaning of the plain text of the Ninth Amendment.
In Dobbs, the majority opinion (twice) misrepresented that the Ninth Amendment was a "reservation of rights to the people." The majority abused that lie about the meaning of the Ninth Amendment to justify the following contention and conclusion (which blatantly violated the Ninth Amendment): "The Constitution makes no express reference to a [person’s] right to [do something with such person’s own body], and therefore those who claim that it protects such a right must show that the right is somehow implicit in the constitutional text."
Clearly, the Ninth Amendment does not state a reservation of rights. It clearly states a rule of construction that expressly prohibits judges from doing what six SCOTUS justices did, above. This is super simple and super straightforward. No judge (or lawyer) worthy of the title could read the Ninth Amendment and fail to see that it stated a clear command about how our "Constitution" absolutely "shall not be construed." Our "Constitution" NEVER can "be construed to deny or disparage" ANY rights "retained by the people" because of any mere "enumeration in the Constitution" of "certain rights."
The Dobbs majority blatantly violated the Ninth Amendment by focusing on the (irrelevant) fact that "[t]he Constitution makes no express reference to a right to [do something specific]" and then using the absence of an "express reference to a [person’s] right to [do something specific with such person’s own body]" to justify shifting the burden of proof to people asserting our rights.
I'm not sure I could have done more justice to Blackman's arrogance and ignorance than he did to himself with his final paragraph. Blackman promised his fellow religious zealots, "If I ever become Chief Justice for a day (Lord help us all) I would sandblast the phrase 'Equal Justice Under Law' off the west pediment" of the building that houses the U.S. Supreme Court. As Chief Justice, Blackman would needlessly and ruthlessly deface the building that houses the highest court created by the People and our Constitution specifically to "establish Justice" and "secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves." Our Constitution and our highest court were ordained and established, in very significant part, to protect us from the religious zealotry of people like Blackman.
Blackman should think about why it is that he has the freedom to be a religious zealot in this country. As federal law (5 U.S.C. 3331) requires, multitudes of Americans (including federal judges) promised to "support and defend" our "Constitution" against "all enemies, foreign and domestic" and to "bear true faith and allegiance to" our "Constitution." Many generations of Americans (and people aspiring to be Americans) suffered and sacrificed much to fulfill their oaths. We did so because we believe and believed that our Constitution secures equal justice for all.
I served as a U.S. Army Ranger stationed in Savannah, Georgia. Nathanael Greene, one of the most conscientious, diligent and successful generals of the Revolutionary War is buried and memorialized in Savannah. In 1777, Greene sent a letter to John Adams, who was serving as the equivalent of today's Secretary of Defense. In his letter, Greene wrote words that summed up the essence of the Declaration of Independence, the Revolutionary War, and our Constitution's explicit emphasis on Justice and Liberty. Greene's words summed up why we served: "I can assure you, I am not fighting for a change of Masters, but to have none but the Law."
If Blackman is half as smart as he thinks he is, he would think twice about trying to erase and deface Americans' commitment to equal justice under the law.
I think Equal Justice Under Law fits exactly what Barret is saying. It's not "do what I think is right," it's equally dispense justice according to what the law says. And that's exactly right. Judges are not meant to be deciding what the best choice is in the abstract, but to follow the laws set out and determine what trumps when the different laws conflict. I've been growing more appreciative of Barret's writing her last few opinions, and this excerpt made me preorder her book. I'll be curious to read the whole thing.
I think Equal Justice Under Law fits exactly what Barret is saying. It's not "do what I think is right," it's equally dispense justice according to what the law says.
How, in your view, does
"equally dispense justice according to what the law says"
differ from
"make your ruling according to what the law says"
Is the first merely a self-basting pablum designed to make the rubes think well of the law ? Can we not think of unjust laws ?
Methinks, contra Barrett, that it is not a tautological slogan - ie that what you get under a correctly and honestly applied law is ipso facto, justice. It is a nod to the fact that laws are sometimes unjust and a suggestion that the judge may tweak the rules, at need, to arrive at a "just" result. SRG2 supplies the canonical formulation.
This suggestion dare not speak its name, because such tweaks are obviously contrary to the rule of law. And since the rule of law is "a good thing" we must pretend that everything else we like - like justice - comports with it.
As a slogan it has its place as an encouragement to legislators to try to write laws that are just. As an invocation to the judicial branch it is an open invitation to yield to the temptation to pull rulings from one's fundament, a la Breyer. Consequently I second Josh's sandblasting proposal. The Supreme Court is exactly the wrong place for that slogan.
.
It's slightly annoying how lawyers and others use "split the baby" to refer to some sort of 50/50 resolution, essentially meaning the same as "split the difference." As Barret explained this is pretty far off from the origin of the phrase, which involved a righteously 100/0 resolution - arrived at by the threat of a 0/0 solution.
Here Blackman persists in using the phrase to mean the same thing as "split the difference" even after being set straight by Barret. Oh well.