The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
"Title VI Must Be Applied Consistent with First Amendment Principles"
A federal district court discusses how the First Amendment limits liability for "hostile environment harassment" based on "speech on matters of public concern" in universities (public or private). And the reasoning may extend to Title VII liability on workplaces as well.
An excerpt from Judge John Cronan's long decision today in Gartenberg v. Cooper Union (S.D.N.Y.) (I expect to blog more later about other facets of the case [UPDATE: see this post]); note that the court's logic applies to Title VII liability in workplaces as well, especially since it cites precedents and articles that focus on Title VII:
Title VI makes it unlawful for institutions that receive federal funding to discriminate against participants in their programs on account of race, color, or national origin. In the educational context, actionable discrimination includes an institution's "deliberate indifference" to known instances of student-on-student harassment that are "'severe, pervasive, and objectively offensive' and discriminatory in effect." …
Title VI Must Be Applied Consistent with First Amendment Principles, Even When the Defendant is a Private Institution.
At the outset, Cooper Union maintains that Gartenberg's hostile environment claims are based largely on protected political speech by pro-Palestinian members of its community, and are therefore foreclosed by the First Amendment. Indeed, Gartenberg's Complaint—which alleges liability predicated, in part, on a demonstration on a public sidewalk concerning the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, the distribution of fliers supporting the Palestinian cause, a controversial "art display" advocating violent resistance to "colonialism," and a speech given by Dr. Bartov about the Holocaust—is "rife … with [F]irst [A]mendment overtones." DeAngelis v. El Paso Mun. Police Officers Ass'n (5th Cir. 1995).
Gartenberg responds that the First Amendment has no relevance to her hostile environment claims. Gartenberg contends that Cooper Union is a private institution and that "[i]n contrast to students at public or state institutions, students at private colleges do not enjoy First Amendment protections." Going on, Gartenberg argues that regardless of whether Cooper Union is itself bound by the First Amendment, it would "still have the authority under the U.S. Constitution, and a responsibility under Title VI, to punish students who harass their Jewish peers on campus and thereby interfere with the victims' ability to participate in school activities."
Gartenberg's argument is unpersuasive.
A statute that burdens protected speech must comport with the First Amendment regardless of whether it does so directly, such as by prohibiting certain speech outright, or indirectly, such as by requiring a court adjudicating a "civil lawsuit between private parties" to apply a rule of law that has the effect of "impos[ing] invalid restrictions on [the defendant's] constitutional freedom[] of speech." N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan (1964); see also Kingsley R. Browne, Title VII as Censorship: Hostile-Environment Harassment and the First Amendment, 52 Ohio St. L.J. 481, 510-11 (1991) ("Although the primary method of enforcement of the harassment prohibition is through civil actions between private parties, imposition of liability by the courts under federal and state statutes easily falls within the definition of 'state action.'"). And as relevant here, requiring schools to censor or punish political speech to avoid liability for a hostile environment would burden not only their students' freedom of expression, but the academic freedom of the institution itself to create an educational environment centered around the free exchange of ideas. See Dube v. State Univ. of N.Y. (2d Cir. 1990) ("[F]or decades it has been clearly established that the First Amendment tolerates neither laws nor other means of coercion, persuasion or intimidation 'that cast a pall of orthodoxy' over the free exchange of ideas in the classroom.").
That a private institution like Cooper Union is generally free to regulate its students' speech without regard for the First Amendment, therefore, is irrelevant to the question of whether Congress may compel it to do so via the threat of civil liability under Title VI. See Yelling v. St. Vincent's Health Sys. (11th Cir. 2023) (Brasher, J., concurring) ("Although a private [institution] can adopt a speech code if it wants, the government usually cannot force people to speak in a particular way."); Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and Workplace Harassment, 39 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 1791, 1817 (1992) ("The government cannot escape First Amendment scrutiny for its speech restriction by forcing someone else, on pain of liability, to implement that restriction.").
In addition, if a given interpretation of a statute "would raise a multitude of constitutional problems" when applied in one context, a court must consider those issues regardless of "whether or not those constitutional problems pertain to the particular litigant before the Court." Title VI, contrary to Gartenberg's suggestion, is not "a chameleon, its meaning subject to change depending on" whether the defendant is private or public institution. The Court therefore cannot ignore the constitutional problems that would inevitably arise in the context of public universities—which, unlike Cooper Union, must respect their students' First Amendment rights—if Title VI required the suppression of core political speech.
Accordingly, the Court must confront the merits of Cooper Union's First Amendment defense. Imposing civil liability on institutions based on their failure to censor or punish offensive speech raises significant constitutional concerns. The First Amendment embodies "the fundamental principle that governments have 'no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.'" Yet "a disparaging comment directed at an individual's sex, race, or some other personal characteristic has the potential to create an 'hostile environment'—and thus come within the ambit of anti-discrimination laws—precisely because of its sensitive subject matter and because of the odious viewpoint it expresses." Saxe v. State Coll. Area Sch. Dist. (3d Cir. 2001) (Alito, J.); see also DeAngelis (explaining that when a hostile environment claim is "founded solely on verbal insults, pictorial or literary matter, the statute imposes content-based, viewpoint-discriminatory restrictions on speech"). Thus, the federal anti-discrimination laws arguably "impose special prohibitions on those speakers who express views on disfavored subjects" by effectively requiring institutions to censor and punish at least some offensive speech concerning matters of race, sex, and other personal characteristics. R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul (1992); see, e.g., Volokh, supra, at 1854-55 ("One person in the lunch room may speak eloquently and loudly about how women are equal to men, and harassment law will not stop him. But when another tries to respond that women are inferior—belong in the home, are unreliable during their menstrual periods, or should not be allowed on the police force—harassment law steps in.").
In part because harassment claims are rarely based on pure political speech, however, few courts have had occasion to address what limits, if any, the First Amendment places on federal anti-discrimination law. But under the Supreme Court's usual First Amendment jurisprudence, a statute that "favors one viewpoint about [a topic] over the other … must satisfy strict scrutiny," meaning that Congress must adopt "the least restrictive means of achieving a compelling state interest." Plus, speech on matters of "public concern"—expression that "can 'be fairly considered as relating to any matter of political, social, or other concern to the community'"—is "entitled to 'special protection' under the First Amendment" and generally "cannot be restricted simply because it is upsetting or arouses contempt." Snyder v. Phelps (2011).
It is also far from clear that most offensive speech that is regularly swept up in harassment cases would fit within the narrow sphere of traditionally recognized categories of unprotected expression, such as the exceptions for incitement, fighting words, true threats, and obscenity. Indeed, "courts have never embraced a categorical 'harassment exception' from First Amendment protection for speech that is within the ambit of federal anti-discrimination laws." Saxe; see also Rodriguez v. Maricopa Cnty. Cmty. Coll. Dist. (9th Cir. 2010) ("Harassment law generally targets conduct, and it sweeps in speech as harassment only when consistent with the First Amendment."). For these reasons, one leading treatise on the First Amendment teaches that "in the rare case in which the particular speech at issue does qualify [as expression on a matter of public concern], the [institution] should be exempted from liability" for a hostile environment. Rodney A. Smolla & Melville B. Nimmer, Smolla & Nimmer on Freedom of Speech § 13:17 (2024).
On the other hand, there is no question that the elimination of discriminatory harassment in employment and in programs receiving federal funding is a compelling government interest. Saxe. And as decades of judicial experience have made all too clear, abusive speech, no less than abusive conduct, can readily slam shut the doors to the workplace or seal the schoolhouse gates. So just as federal anti-discrimination law must provide some breathing space for contentious political expression if First Amendment rights are to survive, the Constitution must tolerate the regulation of at least some offensive speech if the Civil Rights Act is to achieve its promise of unlocking the benefits of employment and education for all Americans. See Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Sexual Harassment, Content Neutrality, and the First Amendment Dog That Didn't Bark, 1994 Sup. Ct. Rev. 1, 48 (1994) ("[P]olitical democracy requires a broad space for unrestricted public discourse, but that space need not be boundless." (internal quotation marks omitted)). And there may yet be a doctrinal basis for regulating offensive speech more closely in those contexts. See Wisconsin v. Mitchell (1993) (citing Title VII "as an example of a permissible content- neutral regulation of conduct"); Avis Rent A Car Sys., Inc. v. Aguilar (2000) (Thomas, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari) (discussing the public-employee-speech and captive-audience doctrines).
Finally, the Court notes that the First Amendment concerns described above cannot be brushed aside in the Title VI context merely because Congress enacted the statute pursuant to its power under the Spending Clause. Because compliance with Title VI (unlike compliance with Title VII and other "mandatory" anti-discrimination statutes) is only required for institutions that voluntarily accept federal funding, one might take the position that to the extent a college or university objects to the First Amendment implications of the statute, its recourse is simply to stop accepting federal education funds. Congress, however, "may not deny a benefit to a person on a basis that infringes his constitutionally protected … freedom of speech even if he has no entitlement to that benefit." Under that principle, known as the "unconstitutional conditions doctrine," a condition imposed in connection with a grant of federal funding would be unconstitutional if Congress could not impose that condition through direct legislation. Accordingly, the fact that an institution could escape Title VI's requirements by declining federal funds does not, by itself, obviate the First Amendment implications of construing Title VI to require censorship of political speech.
The Court Does Not Construe Title VI as Reaching Pure Speech on Matters of Public Concern.
In light of the competing interests described above, courts have emphasized the need to "exercise special caution when applying [anti-discrimination law] to matters involving traditionally protected areas of speech." Honeyfund.com Inc. v. Governor (11th Cir. 2024); see also DeAngelis ("Where pure expression is involved, [anti-discrimination law] steers into the territory of the First Amendment."). And the responsibility of courts to tread lightly when political speech is in the legal crosshairs is particularly important in the context of higher education.
Following that careful approach, the Court concludes that because interpreting Title VI to impose liability for a hostile environment created in part by pure speech on matters of public concern would cast significant doubt on the statute's constitutionality, the Court must adopt a permissible construction of Title VI that avoids placing its application in First Amendment jeopardy…. As relevant to the elements of Gartenberg's Title VI claim that are at issue in this case, three guiding principles emerge that avoid a collision between the First Amendment and anti-discrimination law while still allowing the statute to function effectively.
First, speech "on a matter of public concern, directed to the college community," will generally fail to "constitute unlawful harassment." Rodriguez. This approach is consistent with the objective standard that courts use to assess the hostility element of federal harassment claims: a reasonable person should understand that speech on matters of public concern, directed to the community at large through generally accepted methods of communication, is very different than targeted, personal harassment aimed at a particular person. See Yelling (Brasher, J., concurring) (explaining that "speech on public matters is inherently less likely to create a hostile [] environment than speech on private matters"); DeAngelis (declining to find a hostile work environment based on a series of satirical columns published in a police union's newsletter that "derogatorily referred to policewomen"). The principle underlying this approach is that a reasonable person should distinguish between the abstract expression of offensive "values, politics, and attitudes" on the one hand, and "remarks that genuinely target and harass" individuals on the other. Smolla & Nimmer, supra § 13:17; see also Volokh, supra, at 1871 (distinguishing between offensive speech directed at particular individuals in a targeted manner and speech that is not so directed). This is especially true in the context of higher education, where the reasonable student expects (if not hopes) to encounter "rigorous debate and discussion, and the unfettered exchange of ideas" concerning a wide range of controversial topics. Azhar Majeed, The Misapplication of Peer Harassment Law on College and University Campuses and the Loss of Student Speech Rights, 35 J.C. & U.L. 385, 386 (2009).
And by the same token, a reasonable person should perceive offensive political speech communicated through generally accepted means (say, during a debate in the breakroom or in a flier pinned to a bulletin board) differently to offensive messages conveyed in a manner that does not conform to reasonable social expectations (for instance, by vandalizing a hallway). The former is much more likely to be received as good-faith discourse; the latter as an effort to harass, intimidate, or discriminate. Cf. Fallon, supra, at 47 (explaining that the First Amendment should protect "speech or expressive conduct that is reasonably designed or intended to contribute to reasoned debate on issues of public concern" (internal quotation marks omitted)). And on the other side of the equation, restricting the former is far more likely to burden legitimate expressive activity than restricting the latter.
Limiting anti-discrimination statutes like Title VI in this manner does not, however, mean that courts must "fall for the glib assertion that because matters of race and gender are, at the broadest level of abstraction, clearly issues of public concern, all racist and sexist remarks automatically qualify" for First Amendment protection. Applying federal anti-discrimination law consistent with First Amendment principles does not, in other words, require courts to shield all "derogatory epithets" of marginal value or to protect speech "even about political matters, that is so persistent or patently harassing that it could not be reasonably designed to contribute to reasoned debate." Fallon, supra, at 47. To be sure, political speech need not match the caliber of expression associated "with Marcus Cicero or Henry Clay" to receive constitutional protection, Yelling (Brasher, J., concurring), but neither does the First Amendment demand that low-value speech of the sort "that can give an abusive character even to political discussion" be protected in all contexts. And as noted, the way in which a message is communicated can matter just as much to its harassing character as what is said.
At the end of the day, what is important is that the law provide sufficient "breathing space for First Amendment freedoms." Accordingly, the Court does not construe Title VI as allowing for liability based on speech that is reasonably designed or intended to contribute to debate on matters of public concern, and that is expressed through generally accepted methods of communication.
Second, the need to avoid a collision between Title VI and the First Amendment counsels in favor of an even more limited application of the already strict deliberate indifference standard. Under that standard, an institution may only be held liable when its response (or lack thereof) to known instances of student-on-student harassment was "clearly unreasonable in light of the known circumstances." It is "axiomatic," however, that "the government may not silence speech because the ideas it promotes are thought to be offensive." Rodriguez. Nor may it conscript private institutions to act as censors by dangling the threat of civil liability for a hostile environment. That is nowhere truer than in the educational context, where "the Supreme Court's academic-freedom jurisprudence principally protects the 'marketplace of ideas' in the university and prevents government intrusion."
The First Amendment therefore "demands substantial deference to [a] college's decision not to take action against" students who engage in expressive activity on matters of public concern and instead requires courts to "defer to colleges' decisions to err on the side of academic freedom." For these reasons, it will usually be difficult—if not impossible—to show that a college or university acted in a clearly unreasonable manner under Title VI where its acts of alleged deliberate indifference consist of its refusal to punish political speech directed at the college community through reasonable means.
Finally, construing Title VI not to reach instances of pure speech on matters of public concern, or an institution's failure to censor or punish the same, does not mean that such expression is irrelevant to determining whether actionable harassment occurred. To make out a hostile environment claim, a plaintiff must plead (and then prove) not only that they suffered objectively severe or pervasive harassment, but that the harassment was motivated, at least in part, by a protected characteristic. And courts have long recognized that there is "no constitutional problem with using … offensive speech as evidence of motive or intent." Saxe; Mitchell (explaining that the First Amendment does not preclude evidence of discriminatory motive under the federal anti-discrimination statutes).
So for example, evidence that a white student attended a Ku Klux Klan rally, though protected expression or association in and of itself, may properly be considered in determining whether unprotected harassing conduct directed at his African-American classmates was motivated by race. See Dawson v. Delaware (1992) ("[T]he Constitution does not erect a per se barrier to the admission of evidence concerning one's beliefs and associations … simply because those beliefs and associations are protected by the First Amendment."). Accordingly, when a hostile environment claim is based on both protected speech and unprotected conduct, a court must still consider the entire record in determining whether the harassment was discriminatory in nature.
This strikes me as generally a sound and important analysis, and one that's likely to be highly influential. I don't entirely agree with it on all points, but I think that on balance it's a major step forward in this area of the law.
UPDATE: Here's how the court applies the reasoning above to particular allegations by the plaintiffs:
As foreshadowed above, many of the alleged instances of harassment detailed in Gartenberg's Complaint are examples of pure speech on matters of public concern. For instance, Gartenberg alleges that on October 25, 2023, pro-Palestinian students demonstrated on the sidewalk adjacent to the Foundation Building and chanted slogans concerning the Israeli-Palestinian conflict. Gartenberg also points to fliers that were distributed around the Cooper Union campus inviting students to "[c]elebrate the 36th anniversary of the First Intifada" and to a vigil hosted by Cooper Union's SJP chapter to "grieve and honor all those killed by decades of Israeli occupation and imperial violence."
Similarly, she points to articles in Cooper Union's student-run newspaper by the MSA and the BSU disputing Jewish students' account of the library incident and criticizing "the conflation of Zionism and Judaism" as "manipulative, exploitive, and racist"; an alumni letter that "attempted to justify the sickening Hamas attack of October 7"; an "art display" that included the words "RESIST COLONIALISM FROM THE BRONX TO PALESTINE 'BY ANY MEANS NECESSARY'"; and Cooper Union "requiring all students, including Jewish students, taking a core Humanities and Social Sciences class to attend a speech titled 'The Never Again Syndrome: Uses and Misuses of Holocaust Memory and the Weaponization of Language' by anti-Israel activist, Omer Bartov."
Regardless of whether this expression is better characterized as righteous protest in support of a noble cause, as the vulgar celebration of terrorism and antisemitism, or as something in-between, it is not a proper basis on which to impose civil liability on Cooper Union. The content of the protest slogans, fliers, and other expressions described above related to the ongoing Israeli-Palestinian conflict and touched upon topics like Zionism, colonialism, and racism.
Gartenberg's Complaint offers no factual support for its assertion that any of these messages were intended to target particular Jewish students, as opposed to efforts to communicate a political message to the Cooper Union community at large. And apart from a conclusory suggestion that this speech included "threats of violence," the Complaint does not plausibly allege that any of this expressive conduct constituted true threats, incitement, fighting words, obscenity, or any other category of traditionally unprotected speech under the Supreme Court's First Amendment jurisprudence.
To the contrary, as described in the Complaint, this expression qualifies as pure speech on matters of public concern because "it can be fairly considered as relating to [a] matter of political, social, or other concern to the community" and was communicated in a manner reasonably calculated to contribute to an ongoing public debate of considerable political significance. Accordingly, while some of this speech may properly be considered for purposes of Title VI's discriminatory-intent element, it cannot itself support a claim for an objectively hostile educational environment under this Court's interpretation of the statute.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
The obvious fix, of course, is that it's the "deliberate indifference" clause that creates the constitutional problem and that needs to go. Student-on-student harassment is a problem for the regular police just like neighbor-on-neighbor harassment or driver-on-driver conflicts. Universities should have no part in resolving student-on-student conflicts.
Okay, maybe a university could offer non-binding mediation services without stepping over the line but that's it. Anything legally binding should be dealt with through the police, not university administrators.
Just read the update. The university "requiring all students, including Jewish students" to take a class that, for the purposes of argument, I will assume could be objectively proven to be offensive would not be student-on-student behavior and perhaps could still trigger Title VI liability. That would implicate the university's own free-speech rights but that is a much simpler analysis than liability for student-on-student behavior.
But if the rules are known by students before acceptance then you can force resolutions. There are always difficult cases but you can enforce silence on both sides. IF you are a real college honoring the contract that Ma and Pa pay big bucks for.
'Binding as a condition of contract' implies (and I would argue, requires) an absence of government coercion in the terms of the contract. If the government is compelling the inclusion of certain terms in the contract, the government has made the contract writer into a state agent and re-incorporated the constitutional problem.
Actually, I've wondered that for awhile with both racial and sexual harassment. Certainly neither are within any of the normal first amendment exceptions.
I can understand when it's more than just speech, but plenty of workplace harassment cases turn purely on speech.
You can call someone a n****r on the street and the First Amendment will protect you from any government sanction. (You might be subjected to private violence in response, but that's the risk you take.) If your private employer says you can't call your co-workers "n****rs" on the job, you don't have a First Amendment right to disregard your employer's instructions. Same with a public employer, though for slightly different reasons. Both employers can also say you can't call your co-workers "a******s" on the job. None of that raises a First Amendment issue.
But does the First Amendment prevent the government from telling employers that they cannot permit their employees to call their co-workers n*****s on the job even if the employer doesn't object -- or might even prefer it? (It hasn't attempted to regulate whether you can call your co-workers a******s.) It is hard to see how. If there is a compelling interest in preventing discrimination, and courts recognize that there is, and discrimination is commonly effectuated by speech, and it is, discriminatory speech can be proscribed for the same reason that you can prosecute false speech under oath as perjury -- it's the only way to reach behavior the government has a right to prevent,
Okay, but you are there to learn ANY infringement of that is wrong. I pay a fortune for my kids and I don't care about tent cities, sitins or protests that get you out of doing your homework
"Title VI makes it unlawful for institutions that receive federal funding to discriminate against participants in their programs on account of race, color, or national origin."
Is Jewishness a "race," "color," or "national origin"?
Yes.
If you don't believe me you can look it up.
See this post and this Congressional Research Service report.
Thanks for that. This is why we have professors, and why we should treasure them. All this time I was under the misimpression that only (or primarily) NAZIs talked about the Jewish "race," but now I see that it's also the Supreme Court of the United States.
IRL, I probably knew this intuitively, but preferred not to think about it. But I guess we can just say that words were understood differently back then, and even though you'd have to be a NAZI to say that today, back then, it was pretty much self-evidently true. Because things change, and an understanding of one time doesn't necessarily apply to another.
I dont see the justification for the theory that in the harassment context the 1A only operates to prevent protected speech from being adduced as evidence of a hostile work environment when that speech is on a matter of public concern.
In other words, protected speech on issues of private concern should likewise receive protection.
The only 1A areas where speech on issues of public concern receives heightened protection is in the defamation context (higher mens rea) and for public employee speech. The first situation is a well established category of protected speech, and the second is justified by the need for the government to exert some degree of discipline over its own employees.
As noted, there is no harassment exception to the 1A. In the protected speech context, Courts would never accept a law under strict scrutiny analysis when the goal is just to protect people from offense. Judge Cronan's analysis has been warped by the fact that the hostile environment cause of action has for so long evaded first amendment scrutiny, and by the long running civil religion and paranoia over racism that has emerged in recent decades.
The following passage is particularly concerning:
"Limiting anti-discrimination statutes like Title VI in this manner does not, however, mean that courts must 'fall for the glib assertion that because matters of race and gender are, at the broadest level of abstraction, clearly issues of public concern, all racist and sexist remarks automatically qualify' for First Amendment protection. Applying federal anti-discrimination law consistent with First Amendment principles does not, in other words, require courts to shield all 'derogatory epithets' of marginal value or to protect speech 'even about political matters, that is so persistent or patently harassing that it could not be reasonably designed to contribute to reasoned debate.'"
Even under Judge Cronan's more speech-protective framework, there will be plenty of wiggle room for plaintiffs to argue that a particular racist/sexist remark is not sufficiently geared towards an issue of public concern (maybe because an employee makes the subject remark in a humorous manner, and the plaintiff argues that people normally dont speak about issues of public concern so flippantly). Judge Cronan's analysis also doesn't address the fact that there is widespread disagreement over what expressions/phrases are racist, in what contexts, and by which speakers.
To the extent any protected speech is allowed to form the basis of the hostile environment cause of action (i.e.: to the the extent it is eligible to be adduced as evidence of severe and pervasive discrimination), it should only be speech that fits into the putative one-to-one 1A exception that Professor Volokh has sketched out.
Even here there is a concern that Courts will eventually shoehorn speech into this category where the speaker is not directly targeting/harassing an individual. There might be cases where a speaker makes an allegedly racist/sexist remark within earshot of the plaintiff, but not necessarily directed to her. There will be some gray areas, but the chilling effect will be lower if only one-to-one speech (and other unprotected categories) can be adduced as evidence of a hostile work environment.
To mitigate the risk that the one-to-one category sweeps up too many instances of indirectly targeted speech, plaintiffs should have to establish some evidence of intentionality (i.e.: that although the speaker did not make the remarks directly to the plaintiff, he clearly intended that she hear them).
Another requirement for establishing that speech falls into the one-to-one exception should be that it is part of a pattern of speech targeted at the plaintiff by a specific individual or a group of coordinated individuals. The pattern element would require multiple cases of targeted harassing conduct, and would ensure that employers have at least constructive notice (this would eliminate the prospect of one derogatory remark--such as a coworker uttering the n-word--being sufficient to make out a hostile environment claim).
The pattern requirement would likewise eliminate another censorious ripple effect of hostile environment claims: as Professor Volokh notes, because a plaintiff can make out a severe and pervasive work environment from the speech of various disparate individuals and from remarks made at different times, employers have an incentive to maximally restrict speech to avoid even approaching the amorphous severe-and-pervasive line.
On the flip side, as opposed to the speech of various disparate employees, employers are perfectly capable of controlling their own speech. Therefore, and contra Judge Walker in his snarky reddit-tier opinion in the Florida Stop WOKE Act case, a hostile work environment claim premised on an employer has creating a hostile work environment by hosting a mandatory DEI training session, poses far less of a 1A concern. Employers can avoid liability very easily in a way that avoids restricting the speech of their employees: simply refrain from hosting training sessions of this nature and making them mandatory.
https://imprimis.hillsdale.edu/religious-liberty-and-the-genius-of-the-american-founding/
It doesn't solve everything but if Freedom of Relgion has its Founding place. , away goes a good deal of problems. And religious sentiment that goes against Constitutional principles are illegal. We proscribe honor killing, suttee, bigamy, slavery. Don't like it? Leave the country
I make a distinction between situations where a reasonable person would be concerned about the safety of his/her/its person and/or property (or that of third parties) and those where said reasonable person would not.
Now as to what a "reasonable person" *is* can be uncertain, and I reject things like "the reasonable lesbian" standard as well as the "reasonable rape survivor" standard that the separatists would like to use.
And the other thing not mentioned here is the liability assumed by the college by precluding the means of self defense, i.e. prohibition on guns (etc.).
https://imprimis.hillsdale.edu/religious-liberty-and-the-genius-of-the-american-founding/
It doesn't solve everything but if Freedom of Relgion has its Founding place. , away goes a good deal of problems. And religious sentiment that goes against Constitutional principles are illegal. We proscribe honor killing, suttee, bigamy, slavery. Don't like it? Leave the country
Gartenberg argues that regardless of whether Cooper Union is itself bound by the First Amendment, it would "still have the authority under the U.S. Constitution, and a responsibility under Title VI, to punish students who
I am reminded of a bit from comedian Bill Hicks, where he rants sarcastically, "You are free...to do as we tell you. You are free...to do as we tell you!"
I wonder if Bill Hicks shorts will pop up on my feeds later. Let's see 🙁
Here is where a free market in work speech would do wonders.
There are anti-Catholic, anti-Semitic , anti-Black work environments and if management could summarily dismiss someone , say, a gay teacher from a Catholic school, things would perk up.
To have to call in the law and get , what? a ruling that says you can go back to work where you just lodged a serious complaint --- that is no justice. Let what happens anyway happen openly