The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Computer Code Can Be Regulated Because of What It Does, Even If Not Because of What It Says
The D.C. Circuit rejects a First Amendment challenge to the Digital Millennium Copyright Act's anticircumvention and antitrafficking provisions.
From today's D.C. Circuit decision in Green v. U.S. Dep't of Justice, written by Judge David Tatel and joined by Judges Judith Rogers and Justin Walker:
In this digital age, when content creators choose to make their copyrighted materials—like books, movies, and music—available online, they employ computer code to block unauthorized access, copying, and use. To fortify the protection offered by that code, Congress enacted the Digital Millennium Copyright Act, which makes it unlawful to bypass such technological measures. The question in this case, which comes to us at the preliminary injunction stage, is whether the statute is likely to violate the First Amendment rights of two individuals who write computer code designed to circumvent those measures. The district court answered no, and we agree….
[T]he Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA) … "back[s] with legal sanctions the efforts of copyright owners to protect their works from piracy behind digital walls such as encryption codes or password protections." … First, the statute's anticircumvention provision prohibits "circumvent[ing] a technological measure that effectively controls access to a [copyrighted work]." A "technological measure," also called a "technological protection measure," effectively controls access to a work if it, "in the ordinary course of its operation, requires the application of information, or a process or a treatment, with the authority of the copyright owner, to gain access to the work." For example, Netflix requires a password to access its digital movie catalog, and electronic books contain code that prevents readers from copying the book into another format. Circumvention occurs when someone descrambles a scrambled work, decrypts an encrypted work, or otherwise avoids, bypasses, removes, deactivates, or impairs a technological measure, without authority from the copyright owner.
The statute's second principal provision—the antitrafficking provision—works together with the anticircumvention provision to target the technological tools that facilitate circumvention. It prohibits "manufacturing, importing, offering to the public, providing, or otherwise trafficking in any technology, product, service, device, component, or part thereof" if it (1) "is primarily designed or produced for the purpose of circumventing a technological measure that effectively controls access to a [copyrighted] work;" (2) "has only limited commercially significant purpose or use other than to circumvent;" or (3) "is marketed … for use in circumventing." Those who violate either the anticircumvention or antitrafficking provision are subject to civil actions and criminal sanctions….
Plaintiff Matthew Green, a security researcher and computer science professor at Johns Hopkins University, wants to publish an academic book "to instruct readers in the methods of security research," which will include "examples of code capable of bypassing security measures." He is concerned that including "instructions in both English and in software code" for "circumvent[ing] technological protection measures" would likely violate the DMCA.
Plaintiff Andrew "bunnie" Huang, an inventor and electrical engineer, wants to create and sell a device called "NeTVCR." His device contains computer code capable of circumventing High-Bandwidth Digital Content Protection, a technological protection measure that prevents digital content from being copied or played on unauthorized devices. He also intends to publish that computer code to "communicate to others how the technology works and encourage them to discuss edits to improve the code." Huang fears that distribution of the code contained in his NeTVCR device "could [risk] prosecut[ion] under [the DMCA]."
Claiming that the code they write qualifies as speech protected by the First Amendment, Green and Huang brought a pre-enforcement action challenging the DMCA on facial and as-applied First Amendment grounds. [For procedural reasons, the facial challenge was not properly before the D.C. Circuit. -EV] … As to Green's as-applied challenge, the district court concluded that his planned publication was unlikely to implicate section 1201(a) because the book would be designed, used, and marketed for educational purposes rather than for the purpose of circumvention…. [But] the district court found that Huang was unlikely to succeed on his as-applied claim and denied him preliminary injunctive relief….
"In First Amendment cases, the likelihood of success will often be the determinative factor in the preliminary injunction analysis." To succeed on the merits, Huang must show that the DMCA is unconstitutional as applied to his alleged speech activity. We analyze as-applied First Amendment claims in three steps. First, we "decide whether [the activity at issue] is speech protected by the First Amendment." Second, we determine whether the regulation at issue is content based or content neutral, i.e., "if it 'applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed.'" This sets the level of scrutiny we apply at the third step: strict scrutiny for content-based statutes and intermediate scrutiny for content-neutral statutes.
Step one gives us no trouble. Huang wants to sell his NeTVCR device. The device contains "code designed to circumvent certain access controls," which Huang will also publish so that those who own an earlier iteration of his device may upgrade it, and the public may edit and improve his code. According to Huang, writing and communicating computer code capable of circumventing technological protection measures qualifies as First Amendment protected speech. But we have no need to address that question because the government never challenged that proposition in its brief, and at oral argument it conceded that "if you write code so somebody can read it," it is "expressive" speech. All of our sister circuits to have addressed the issue agree…. "Instructions that communicate information comprehensible to a human qualify as speech whether the instructions are designed for execution by a computer or a human (or both).") … "[B]ecause computer source code is an expressive means for the exchange of information and ideas about computer programming," it is protected by the First Amendment ….
We turn then to whether the DMCA "'target[s] speech based on its communicative content'—that is, if it 'applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed.'" It does not. The DMCA's anticircumvention and antitrafficking provisions target not the expressive content of computer code, but rather the act of circumvention and the provision of circumvention-enabling tools. To be sure, the DMCA may incidentally make it more difficult to express things with computer code if that code also facilitates circumvention, but that expressive activity is not the statute's target…. [T]he DMCA "is [not] concerned with whatever capacity [code] might have for conveying information to a human being." Rather, it applies to code "solely because of its capacity to instruct a computer."
The Supreme Court's recent free speech case, City of Austin v. Reagan National Advertising of Austin, LLC (2022), is virtually dispositive. There, the Court rejected a First Amendment challenge to a city ordinance that distinguished between signs advertising products not located near the sign (prohibited) and signs advertising products located near the sign (permitted). Rejecting the idea that "a regulation cannot be content neutral if it requires reading the sign at issue," the Court emphasized that the ordinance cared about the expressive message on a sign "only to the extent that it informs the sign's relative location"; "[a] sign's substantive message itself is irrelevant."
The same logic applies here. Although the DMCA requires reading computer code to determine what digital act the code carries out, it is nonetheless content neutral because, in the words of City of Austin, it cares about the expressive message in the code "only to the extent that it informs" the code's function. The code's "substantive message itself is irrelevant." Indeed, this case is easier than City of Austin because the sign ordinance regulated speech as speech, whereas the DMCA looks only to the code's function, not its expressive content. Accordingly, the DMCA is content neutral and subject to intermediate scrutiny, a test it easily survives.
Under intermediate scrutiny, we will sustain a content-neutral statute if "it furthers an important or substantial governmental interest; if the governmental interest is unrelated to the suppression of free expression; and if the incidental restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is no greater than is essential to the furtherance of that interest." Congress enacted the DMCA to combat fears of "massive piracy" in the digital environment. It intended that section 1201(a) would "create[ ] the legal platform for launching the global digital on-line marketplace for copyrighted works," so that content owners would be willing to "make available via the Internet … movies, music, software, and literary works." In its 2017 study of section 1201, the Register of Copyrights found that the DMCA continues to serve the "essential" purpose of protecting "the right of copyright owners to exercise meaningful control over the terms of access to their works online," and declined to "recommend broad changes to the statute's overall scope." U.S. Copyright Office. The government's evidence makes clear that "without adequate protection against infringing serial copying," content owners "would not disseminate their valuable copyrighted [digital] content."
Huang's NeTVCR device would, by design, "permit virtually anything displayable on a modern television screen to be recorded in the clear and made available online" by making obsolete the technological protection measure it targets. This would "eviscerate virtually every single video content delivery protection system exposing valuable copyrighted video content to massive infringement," gutting the government's substantial interest in ensuring the broadest distribution of copyrighted materials. Huang, who spends most of his brief addressing strict scrutiny, offers no meaningful response and is thus unlikely to succeed on the merits….
Congratulations to Daniel Tenny of the DoJ, who argued the case for the government.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Where are we with the Disney copyright issue?
Isn't Steamboat Willie supposed to be public domain this year or next?
Supposedly the media corporations no longer have any big desire to extend copyright terms even further because they're so nice now/due to the changed political climate.
But if we’re being honest with ourselves the Mouse has already won this fight. Copyrights are already ludicrously and unconstitutionally long. To go further the cost to hire lawyers alone would probably be more expensive than the pennies they’d get from century old cartoons.
There is no point except to pour salt on their defeated enemy. Which they’d do if they could but given the risk of reminding the public of their shenanigans and the trouble of digging out spare change out of their pocket, they’d rather take their fat sack of loot and go home, ‘graciously’ leaving us with100 year old scraps and the illusion of victory at last.
I'll grant you ludicrous, but how is it unconstitutional?
Well, the constitution does say 'for limited times'. Currently that can mean well over 100 years. At some point - 100, 1000, 10000 years - it's not seeming very 'limited'.
Specifically, it says, "To promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries;"
So at the latest, per the actual text of the Constitution, these rights ought to die with the author or inventor.
Is it your view that, say, a patent isn't a property right? For example, if I get a patent for a better mousetrap, I can't sell that patent right to someone else? If I do sell that right to Acme Corp, but get hit by a bus walking home after signing the contract, Acme just lost everything? That seems pretty odd; does Acme have to take out a life insurance policy on me in order to not risk losing its shirt?
For copyright, US Grant famously dictated his memoirs from his deathbed precisely to provide for his family after his death (I don't think presidents got a pension then). Your version of things would make it impossible for an author to do that.
It makes a lot more sense to me to treat patents and copyrights as ordinary property rights that can be inherited, sold, etc., subject to ordinary rules of ownership. You still want to 'promote the progress' even if the inventor or author is old or ill.
But for how long? To provide for their great * 8 grandchildren's financial stability? The founders wanted a limit. As currently contemplated, there's not a practical limit.
I will grant that you make a strong argument for copyrights to be treated as ordinary property rights that can be sold or that can survive the holder's death. On the other hand, the actual enumerated power is for Congress to promote the progress of science and the arts. "By securing for limited times ..." is the modifier that specifies precisely how Congress may carry out their responsibility.
When a copyright regime begins to inhibit the net progress of science and the arts, they no longer pass constitutional muster. Granted, that is a value judgement that could be debated. But I think it is beyond debate that a monopoly grant of infinite duration is a net bad.
Exactly. As an example, Arthur Conan Doyle died in 1930, over 92 years ago. It's outrageous that ANYTHING he wrote is still copyrighted.
Nothing he wrote is still copyright, at least in the USA. His copyrights expired in 2000, 70 years after his death.
"But I think it is beyond debate that a monopoly grant of infinite duration is a net bad."
As I commented above, I agree. Equally so, terminating it too soon - for everyone by limiting the term to 1 day, or from those who die early by making it not inheritable - is bad.
Just off the cuff, the original (20 years??) seemed pretty reasonable. You can make reasonable arguments for longer periods; if I come up with a better blast furnace design it might take me some years to arrange financing and build my steel mill. I think there are historical examples of inventors losing out in that way. So I wouldn't be overly upset by 30 or 40 years; like any line drawing, any point on the spectrum has advantages and disadvantages. But I'm in fervent agreement that the current century plus scheme is ridiculous; congress should be ashamed.
20 years is for patents, we're talking about copyrights. I do agree though that copyright duration should be similar to that of patents.
If that means that Bruce Springsteen no longer owns the rights to music from the 80s, that's too damn bad.
In fairness, copyright rights are far more limited i.e., to a particular work. Patents also don't have anything like fair use.
Fair point. A longer copyright period could be justified based on that, but nowhere near 120 years.
Look, I'm appealing to the clear text of the clause here: It's supposed to encourage science and the arts by giving authors and inventors a temporary government privilege.
Never forget that: Copyright and patents are not natural property, they are privileges the government creates to accomplish an end.
The author may be able to sell the use of this privilege, but if they were only given it for life in the beginning, why would it get longer if they sold it?
Sure, this is going to modestly discourage innovation by people who know they're soon to die. That's very little innovation.
The Supreme Court addressed this in Eldred v. Ashcroft. IMO a terrible decision.
Agree. The Eldred plaintiffs were spot on in pretty much everything they said.
But even they did not go far enough, because it is not enough to limit copyright to the author’s lifetime. Copyright goes beyond its legitimate purpose when it is extended beyond the duration that was in the law when the work was produced, since any additional term was clearly not necessary to incentivize production of the work.
The other problem with a law like DMCA, though, is one that should have been addressed here, namely that most if not all "digital rights management" systems go well beyond enforcing an author's rights under copyright law -- they enforce rights the author or vendor doesn't actually have. For example, the "right" to prevent the owner of a video DVD from skipping past an ad that plays every time any part of the movie is played.
I want to see a case that at least allows circumvention tech to be created and sold when it only circumvents enforcement of these non-rights.
In many ways, the court is right in that the Constitution just says "limited." I'm not sure it's appropriate for a court to make a judgment as to how "limited" it should be.
The real problem is that the Constitution was written assuming that Congress would act in good faith, and the powers it granted Congress were based on that assumption. That obviously is not the case anymore
For steamboat willie specifically, they've been using it in their intros so this may be an intentional ploy to get it trademarked. But I'm not sure how they'd make that work for the rest of their library.
"Steamboat Willie" is now probably also behind these technological measures...
Which never expire. The Constitution is quite explicit in its requirement "for a limited time." Since it violates this provision, the DMCA is unConstitutional on its face.
Fun DMCA fact: it's not actually illegal to circumvent copy protection systems like HDCP (vs. access protection systems or selling devices that do it).
If we're going to treat computer code as a tool then it should be subject to patent law not copyright where it can be locked up and forgotten about for a century or more thanks to Disney.
Computer code does not do *anything* ... it is simply a message that can be interpreted by a device to something. It can be interpreted by a toddler to do something else.
It depends on who's code you are talking about
01 00 10 11 01 10 11 10 11 10 10 00 01 10 10 10 10 00 10 10 10
and I mean it!!!
01 01 10 11 00 10
Any copyright holder that thinks that HDCP technically provides any sort of copy protection is mistaken.
But apparently the DMCA does provide legal protection that stops innovative new products from ever reaching the market.
This results in the purveyors of circumvention information to release it anonymously, or if a profit is sought, within a low risk jurisdiction.
That's kind of the point. If the "technological protection measures" were foolproof, there'd be no need for the DMCA. The purpose of the DMCA is so that the tech / media industries can get by with less intrusive and costly protection measures, since the DMCA adds legal protection on top.
You still have to do a protection measure, but, like HDCP, it can be weak. It serves the same purpose as a fence with a No Trespassing sign: you could hop the fence easily enough, or thwart HDCP, but not accidentally. You're on notice that if you do it, you're intentionally breaking the law.
The argument made in the opinion that this restriction on computer code is NOT "content based.., i.e., ...'applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed'", rather than content neutral, is absolutely self-evident nonsense. The content is precisely what is triggering the violation of the DMCA.
The opinion is surprisingly short, and I also found that to be a glaring weakness. It’d be like a law banning “books intended to be placed in pews and used to synchronize vocal pitch among congregants,” and then deciding that it’s content-neutral because “the substantive message itself is irrelevant” and the law “looks only to the book’s function, not its expressive content.”
Would such a law only be subject to intermediate scrutiny? It would probably fail it, so maybe that's ok, but it feels wrong to me.
Arriving at less than strict scrutiny was clearly the motive.
Maybe its ok to ban this kind of content (like, maybe, "how to forge checks", though even them maybe not) but for a judge to just lie about what he is doing is no way to gain respect for the courts and legal process.
tbh, I thought the government's concession was broader than unnecessary. It's hard to come up with situations where the relevant 'expressive content' requires ready-to-compile source.... real-world scientific papers, etc. use snippets, pseudocode, object diagrams, etc. instead.
The law moves at the speed of a sloth, but the Internet moves at the speed of light. The technical protection that is the subject of the NeTVCR suit is High-Definition Copy Protection (HDCP). As an actual security measure, HDCP is a dead letter, and has been for more than two decades. Not only has a cryptographic master key long ago been leaked to the wild, reverse-engineering it is such a trivial exercise that no one bothers. As Ed Felten noted twelve years ago now, “The main practical effect of HDCP has been to create one more way in which your electronics could fail to work properly with your TV.”
One thing for sure is that any law which attempts to forbid the creation of tools to defeat cryptography is a bad one, IMHO. You just need to make the act of breaking a cryptographic seal a crime, period. How you broke the seal is really irrelevant.
So, assuming the businesses who fund Congress aren’t fools nor idiots, the question is why this particular law was given to the government to be passed. Well, it turns out that there’s a licensing scheme associated with this particular cryptographic method. Well, then. Maybe the law wasn’t intended to hurt tool makers. Maybe it was intended to protect a very specific flow of payments.
Source: Understanding the HDCP Master Key Leak.
I don't understand your point; the DMCA doesn't address "a very specific" method, but all of them, then in existence or to be in existence in the future.
Truthfully, I'm having a hard time seeing the difference between prohibiting writing code that breaks encryption from prohibiting the distribution of locksmithing tools.
That said, talking about either should not be a crime, and my understanding is that DMCA does that.
I think the court here is skipping over the use/possession distinction. I can own books describing how to commit crimes, perhaps in extensive detail. How to synthesize illegal drugs, for instance. Printing them, selling them, buying them, possessing them, is not a crime. Using them to commit the crime is. But, then, using retorts and burners to synthesize illegal drugs is a crime, too, because the actual synthesis is.
Using the book to commit the crime can be an element of the crime, but I don't see how publishing it can properly be a crime.
I mean, even Hit Man: A Technical Manual for Independent Contractors has never actually been held to be illegal to publish, it has never even resulted in the publisher losing a civil case in court! Paladin Press just settled out of court to stop bleeding legal expenses from defending themselves, after their insurer refused them further coverage.
I really don't see how this can survive appeal.
The first amendment issue I see is that if a person wants to make a response video to a work who's access is restricted by digital locks such as HDCP they would be unable to quote the original via a short video clip. It's quite common in written works to quote the arguments of those that go before us, but it seems that in video this often technologically impossible even though the usage may very well fall under the Fair Use exceptions to copyright claims.
The DC Circuit's decision copies directly from the Second Circuit's in _Reimerdes_, who were first to get this **completely wrong**.
This is what we get for not requiring an intro programming class for law students.
Computer code expresses *exactly* what it does. Like, provably (although sometimes people misunderstand what the code expresses, and that's how we get bugs). Expression and function here cannot be separated. When the court writes "The DMCA’s anticircumvention and antitrafficking provisions target not the expressive content of computer code, but rather the act of circumvention and the provision of circumvention-enabling tools", they are technically correct, but Huang and Green's *expression* here is how to circumvent.
What I think happened is the DC Circuit cannot actually understand the code, so they assert that it expresses something different. I hope so anyway.
Because the alternative is acceptance of a **content-neutral** law that says that, while criticism of the president-for-life is fine, any speech that has the *function* of portraying the president-for-life in a bad light is punishable by imprisonment. Speech is free, only insofar as it has no effect.
I would worry that's what the DC Circuit actually meant, except it's pretty clear they simply do not understand programming. Huang (and moreso Green, though he gets a pass here) *intended to express* that DRM can be bypassed.
Finally, the "code is too complicated for us to understand" argument only goes so far. One can, in theory, build a non-circumventing version of Huang's device, in such a way that a very simple script makes it turn into a violator of the DMCA. At that point, it will be very hard to claim that what that script expresses (presumptively legal) is different from what it does.