The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Qualifying Qualified Immunity: Why Constitutional Liability Is Generally Less Fair …
than other kinds of civil liability.
This is the third in a series of posts on my forthcoming article The Fair Notice Rationale for Qualified Immunity. Yesterday I explained why liability that is unpredictable from a defendant's standpoint is unfair: just like retroactive law, it deprives the defendant of the ability to plan, and treats her as a means to an end. That theory helps evaluate the fairness of constitutional liability, and, therefore, the fair notice rationale for the defense of qualified immunity.
My paper argues next that three aspects of constitutional liability make it—in general—more likely to be unpredictable or otherwise unfair than most other forms of civil liability. My argument is not that constitutional liability is the only form of liability that has one or more of these features, but that altogether they make constitutional liability sufficiently unique, as a class, to justify the availability of a defense in at least some cases.
First, constitutional liability is often uniquely unpredictable. Most of the constitutional provisions that form the basis of that liability are vague. Jurists disagree about interpretive methodology. And to the extent a provision requires judicial construction, jurists disagree about what norms or principles should guide it. In short, constitutional doctrine is subject, at least in principle, to more unpredictable changes than most civil liability. Courts interpret provisions for the first time, they apply a doctrine to the states for the first time, they announce a previously unannounced right. They apply doctrinal principles to practices or customs that are longstanding. They tweak doctrine to apply it to new factual contexts. And so on.
This is not to say that constitutional law is arbitrary or entirely unpredictable. Many doctrines are stable, even though they are vague and their application entails discretion. Avid Supreme Court-watchers can usually predict a case's outcome, but the legal basis for that outcome is often unpredictable, even to them.
Some would of course contest the notion that the Court changes constitutional law. Depending on your jurisprudential druthers (and the decision in any case), you might think that doctrinal change—abandoning precedent, extending a rule, etc.—is simply "getting it right," i.e., enforcing the law, not changing it. If you are an originalist, when the Court abandons non-originalist doctrine for one that comports with the original understanding/meaning of the Constitution, it isn't changing constitutional law, only the doctrine that lower courts must apply. If you are an egalitarian Dworkinian, the same applies when the Court decides a case according to a Rawlsian-Dworkinian theory of the good. And so on. My paper means to be agnostic about judicial methodology. My point is only that, from the standpoint of an official, they experience changes to constitutional doctrine as legal change, and often unpredictable change at that. It is unfair to make an officer bear the cost of a court's unpredictable doctrinal change—even if it simply returns the doctrine to the "right answer."
The Supreme Court has implemented this intuition in a number of constitutional situations, usually without exploring its theoretical underpinnings. Consider a recent case. In Barr v. American Association of Political Consultants, Inc., 140 S.Ct. 2335 (2020), the Court considered a law that prohibits robocalls to collect debts. The Court held that an exception for calls to collect debts owed to the government violated the Free Speech Clause. The decision seemed like an obvious application of the existing doctrine's prohibition on content-based restrictions on speech. In a footnote, though, the Court said that no one who had made a robocall in reliance on the provision could be held liable. Why? The Court did not say, but it is at least consistent with the theory that individuals should not pay for constitutional change.
Another feature of constitutional liability that makes it potentially unfair is that, unlike garden-variety torts (or even criminal liability), it often involves the announcement of an unpredictable rule that seems to conflict with a prior-existing duty. Officials must act—it is their job. They often have discretion about means, but they have a legal duty to act. Retroactive constitutional liability, however, creates at least an apparent tension between the duty to act and a constitutional prohibition. It is not a true "conflict" of legal rules because a constitutional norm presumably pre-exists the officer's duty, even if it was not spelled out by the courts, and a constitutional norm trumps lesser legal duties. But to the extent the defendant could not have reasonably predicted the constitutional liability, the official experiences the newly announced rule as creating a conflict, with all the unfairness that entails.
The third aspect of constitutional liability that makes it unique is that, unlike most civil liability, it reflects the community's moral censure. In this respect, it is closer to criminal liability, which cannot be imposed retroactively. Officials uniquely owe a duty to the public. Constitutional liability entails a judgment that the official has breached that duty, one that sounds not only in private wrongdoing, like ordinary torts, but also in public wrongdoing. The wrongdoing is not only against the plaintiff, but in a different, more ephemeral sense, against society at large. This notion of constitutional liability is not well-developed in the literature. It draws on communitarian conceptions of criminal punishment and a newly-championed (but in fact old) conception of torts as moral wrongs rather than merely a matter of distribution of costs and benefits. Unlike many forms of civil liability, the burden of constitutional judgment cannot be outsourced to an employer or an insurance agency through indemnification. It conveys to the defendant, and to the society whose trust he breached, "you didn't just harm the plaintiff, you let us all down. Shame on you."
I have argued that constitutional liability—as a class of torts—has unique aspects that make it, at least in many cases, uniquely unpredictable, at odds with a prior duty, or burdensome. This may demonstrate that the fairness rationale supports qualified immunity in some constitutional cases, but not necessarily in all of them. Tomorrow's post will discuss when this analysis supports qualified immunity, and when it doesn't.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Hmmm... A reasoned defense of the double-standard. I'm not sure I buy it but it's a coherent argument. This will require some thought. Thank you.
Replace constitutional liability, a sign of desperation by the victims of these government thugs. Make it professional standards of due care with ordinary civil liability. Intentional torts get one punitives from personal assets. To deter.
ALL tort law is unpredictable and can be changed because that is how common law works. Courts literally make it up as they go. It's relatively static these days, but still develops as things go. And it's all based on community expectations or norms or whatever you want to call them, too.
Furthermore, individual government officials (typically) aren't paying these judgments out of their pockets, so what "fairness" are you even talking about? It's just a question of when government officials harm people and violate their rights, should the costs of that be born solely by the victim, or by taxpayers as a whole?
If a private citizen reasonably thinks his conduct is constitutionally protected (say, under the First Amendment) and is wrong, too bad! the full force of the government is allowed to crush him. Hopefully, Mr. Chapman endorses doctrinal change based on fair-notice principles that would equally protect private citizens. I see no good reason to think their pocketbooks and freedom are less valuable that those of government agents.
Perhaps we'll also have to wait to see whether he performs any serious cost-benefit analysis that recognizes the unremedied harms the public suffers as a result of QI.
By the way, police, at least, virtually never pay judgments. See Joanna C. Schwartz's NYU Law Review article "Police Indemnification" from 2014. (I'd link to it, but that always prevents my posts from posting.)
From the abstract:
I'm not seeing how any of this applies to the usual QI case, where a public officer, usually a cop, does something plainly illegal, such as robbing someone during a search. Or commits an assault.
Now, these acts properly ought to be prosecuted under criminal law, just as they would be if the perpetrator weren't working for the government. But the law permitting them to be sued, instead, is a recognition of the fact that that just doesn't work, prosecutors routinely refuse to prosecute crimes committed by fellow government officers against the citizenry.
So, nominally, you're suing over a violation of your constitutional rights. But the 'constitutional right' in question isn't the usual freedom of speech, or compensated taking. It's the constitutional right not to have the government commit crimes against you!
For this purpose, the existence of the criminal law that was violated must serve as adequate notice, just as it does for the citizenry.
We still got two days to go. The professor has teased the idea that his fairness-based QI wouldn't apply to a lot of cases that get QI today. Let's see how it plays out.
Nothing about the criminal law or about tort law works. They are in utter failure in all their self stated goals.
Our government was never designed to be micromanaged by courts. It was supposed to be a government of limited powers, and those limitations would be the guardian from infringement. The root cause here (liberals like to talk about that a lot) is that the government does 99% more than what it was designed to do or ought to be doing. If we place governmental authority back in its proper position, most if not all of this goes away.
Can someone put this in a context of follow the money? I can't imagine suing a police officer is particularly productive, unless the union covers the lawsuit payouts, or similar union contracts with a city.
Where are the deep pockets, and how do the lawyers access them? Do you have to be able to sue the officer to be able to sue through them to get at the city?
Usually, the government, or its insurer if it doesn't self-insure, indemnifies the errant official. Sometimes it doesn't, such as in cases where the official isn't acting in the course of his or her employment. A cop who gets into a barroom brawl off duty and without flashing his badge would be neither defended (unless the facts about whether he was acting in the course of his employment were disputed) nor indemnified.
The "deep pockets" are either the government treasury or the insurer. Under current law you do have to sue the officer to get to the deep pockets. That's no big deal because unless the officer does something wrong, there's nothing to sue about.
An off duty cop who didn't flash his badge wouldn't ordinarily get the benefit of QI, anyway.
That might be true if the question needed to be answered. But the off-duty cop in the barroom brawl (or who beat his wife) wasn't acting as a bad cop, he wasn't acting as a cop at all, so he isn't a proper 1983 defendant anyway. Criminal prosecution and state-law tort claims for assault are still on the table, and QI has nothing to do with them.
In practice in a typical QI case, where the underlying law is vague, the court is stuck between two bad choices: impose a cost on the LEO without fair notice, or allow the LEO to impose a cost on a member of the public without fair notice. It seems to me that the latter is always the less acceptable alternative -- not least because an LEO who loses a lawsuit to a plaintiff is not likely to have to pay the award out of his own pocket anyway.
This should be an incredibly simple matter to resolve.
First, as a practical matter, cops don't pay the judgments against them. They virtually always get indemnified. You'll never convince me that the cops should be free to commit massive errors of judgment (or worse), violate my constitutional rights, blind me with a flash bang, destroy my house, and get away with it because some judges pretend against reality that we have to be concerned about the cops' pocketbooks.
Second, obliterating QI is good policy. When the government screws up and harms people, it should pay for that, whether directly or indirectly via indemnification of its agents.
Why is this any different than ordinary negligence liability. Unless there's a case saying not taking X precaution is negligent or non-negligent as a matter of law, you are guessing at whether a jury will find what you did and didn't do to be "reasonable care". And yet, because we think compensating accident victims is important and liability rules result in optimal levels of precaution, we don't worry about the fair notice issue.
To me, "fair notice" seems like special pleading by a group of people who, actually, are paid by the taxpayers and should have a higher degree of regard for people's rights than an ordinary defendant in a negligence case.
It's special pleading for people who have virtually no financial skin in the game because they can expect to be -- and nearly always are -- indemnified.
And even if there is a prior case directly on point, most citizens are highly unlikely to ever be aware of it. Court decisions are not fair notice to most people. A private citizen is always implicitly gambling that they aren't being negligent, because they have no real ability to predict what will be considered negligent in a court of law.
There are recent news stories about a court making GEICO pay a women several million dollars because she got a sexually transmitted disease while having sex in her partner's car. There is nothing even close to fair notice involved in that case.
Great comment, Queenie. You are so well spoken.