The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
Judicial-Judicial Equality Slippery Slopes and the Extension of Precedent
[a] Simply Following Precedent: A Legal Effect Slippery Slope.—One of the most common "A will lead to B" arguments is the argument that judicial decision A would "set a precedent" for decision B. This generally means that (1) A would rest on some justification J and (2) justification J would also justify B.
{Sometimes this sort of argument is made not to illustrate the practical risk that A may lead to B, but to use situation B as an illustration that the underlying theory of rule R is unsound. My discussion here, though, focuses primarily on the practical argument.}
Consider, for instance, the debate about whether the government should be allowed to ban racial, sexual, and religious epithets (beyond those that fit within the existing fighting words and threat exceptions). To uphold such a ban (decision A), the courts would have to give some general justification for why these words should be punishable, essentially creating a new exception to First Amendment protection.
If this justification J were that "epithets add little to rational political discourse and are thus 'low-value speech,' which may be punished," then courts could likewise use this J to uphold bans on flag burning, profanity, and sexually themed (but not obscene) speech, all examples of speech that some argue is of "low value" (result B). In fact, a lower court might feel bound to reach result B because of precedent A's acceptance of justification J. We might call this process a legal effect slippery slope, because B follows from A as an application of an existing legal rule (the obligation to follow precedent).
A related legal effect slippery slope may happen when the justification underlying A is vague enough that it could justify B, even if this effect isn't certain. Thus, suppose the Supreme Court concludes that campus bans on racial, sexual, and religious slurs are constitutional (decision A) because under a totality-of-the-circumstances balancing test the benefits of allowing the bans outweigh the costs (justification K). Proponents of the decision may claim that K wouldn't justify bans on reasoned arguments about biological differences between the sexes, about the supposed immorality of various religious belief systems, or about the supposed failings of various race-based cultures (result B). But it's hard to confidently accept this assurance—K is vague enough that future judges could equally well conclude that K does justify or even require B.
Likewise, a decision and its underlying justification may sometimes grant extra authority to some decisionmakers. Imagine a proposal to ban all racist advocacy, and not just slurs, justified by the theory that racist ideas are wrong and therefore aren't constitutionally protected. A court that accepted this justification would also be setting a precedent that courts have the authority to decide which ideas are wrong and therefore punishable. Once this added authority is accepted, other bad decisions might follow from it: for instance, other judges might use this authority to uphold the suppression of antigovernment ideas, antiwar ideas, or socialist ideas.
So far, the way that A can lead to B is clear: if A sets a precedent that embodies justification J, then lower courts in future cases may feel legally bound to apply J as well. Coordinate courts and the same court would also feel that they ought to apply J, unless there is a strong reason to reject the precedent.
But this legal effect slippery slope doesn't by itself provide much of an argument against result A, because advocates of A could simply urge courts to implement A based on a narrower justification that avoids the excessive breadth or the added authority that would lead to B. For instance, A's advocates could argue that bans on racial, sexual, and religious slurs are constitutional because
- only racially, sexually, and religiously bigoted epithets are "low-value speech" and can thus be prohibited (J1);
- epithets are "low-value speech" and thus may be restricted if a sufficient level of harm is shown—and this level of harm is present for racially, sexually, or religiously bigoted epithets but not for other epithets (J2);
- epithets are "low-value speech," but the Court has the authority to draw such a conclusion only about epithets, not about more reasoned discourse (J3).
Under each of these justifications, A's defenders would argue, bad result B would not necessarily follow as a direct legal effect. Arguing that judicial decision A will lead to B thus requires more than just an assertion that "A will set a precedent for B." Defenders of A can always craft some legal justification for A that distinguishes it from the unwanted result B.
[b] Extension of Precedent as a Judicial-Judicial Equality/Administration Cost Slippery Slope.—But that a distinction between A and B can be drawn doesn't mean that enough future judges will be persuaded by this distinction. Even judges who aren't legally obligated to follow precedent A, because its justification is not literally applicable to current case B, might still feel impelled to extend A beyond its original boundaries.
Consider, for example, justification J1, which would authorize A (racial epithets are punishable but others are protected) but not B (epithets, bigoted or not, are unprotected). Supporters of J1 believe that racial epithets and other epithets are distinguishable, but some Justices might not be persuaded by the distinction. They may particularly oppose restrictions that they see as viewpoint-based. They may oppose giving flag burning, which they see as an anti-American epithet, more protection than other epithets get. Or they might simply conclude that bigoted epithets are not materially different from other epithets, and believe that their duty to treat like cases alike obligates them to treat all epithets the same way. Those Justices might therefore view A as the least satisfactory position, less appealing than either 0 or B.
Say, then, that the Justices form the following blocs (bloc I and bloc II can have any number of Justices between 1 and 4, so long as they add up to 5):
Group | Most prefers | Next preference | Most dislikes | 0→A | A→B | 0→B | Attitude | Voting strength |
I | 0 | B | A | + | "More speech protection is best, but distinguishing bigoted epithets from others is the worst" | 4/3/2/1 | ||
II | A | 0 | B | + | "More speech protection is best, but distinguishing bigoted epithets from others is the worst" | 1/2/3/4 | ||
III | B | A | 0 | + | + | + | "Restrict epithets as much as possible" | 4 |
On a Court where the Justices fall into these blocs, a proposal to move directly from "epithets protected" (0) to "all epithets unprotected" (B) would lose 5-4; only bloc III would prefer B over 0. But a proposal to move from 0 to "bigoted epithets unprotected" (A) would win, with the support of blocs II and III. A proposal to move from A to B would then also win, with the support of blocs I and III. And any proposal to then move from B back to 0 would lose, so long as even one Justice is willing to adhere to precedent even though he substantively prefers 0 to B.
So in our scenario, the bloc II Justices believe that bigoted epithets should be treated differently from other epithets, and their arguments may be logically defensible. But in practice, the arguments were not fully persuasive to blocs I and III, and so the bloc II Justices got what they saw as the worst result—their desire to create an exception for bigoted epithets led to the denial of protection to all epithets. Thus, even with no changes to the Court's personnel, a decision A that doesn't legally command B (and that some Justices see as consistent with the rejection of B) might still bring about B through the equality slippery slope.
Equality slippery slopes may be particularly likely in judicial decisionmaking. Judges are expected to explicitly justify their decisions, and to have principled reasons for the distinctions they draw. They may therefore be more reluctant than legislators or voters to adopt what they see as logically unsound compromises, which is how the judges in bloc I would view result A.
{Equality slippery slopes may be especially likely in areas such as First Amendment law, where equality along some axis (for example, with respect to the viewpoint of the speech) is a strong constitutional norm. Thus, though some Justices (bloc II) may believe that racist epithets are different from other epithets, those that don't accept this position may feel an especially great compulsion—stronger than they would in doctrinal areas where equality is a weaker requirement—to treat the two kinds of epithets similarly.}
This sort of slippery slope may have occurred during the evolution of free speech law in the mid-1900s. Consider decision A, the rule that the government may not restrict political advocacy unless the advocacy creates a "clear and present danger" of some serious harm; decision B, the extension of this protection to entertainment as well as serious political discourse, a step the Court took in the 1948 Winters v. New York decision; and decision C, the extension of this protection to sexually themed speech, at least so long as the speech falls outside the narrow obscenity and child pornography exceptions.
The six-Justice majority in Winters relied in large part on the difficulty of administering any dividing line between political advocacy and entertainment. Likewise, the Court eventually concluded that sexually themed entertainment should be protected alongside other entertainment, largely because of a need to treat ideas—whether about sex or about politics—equally. The clear-and-present-danger cases did not precedentially require the Winters result, and Winters, in turn, did not require the protection of sexually themed speech. But the precedents, combined with the Justices' concerns about administrability and equality, led to the law we have now, through precedential evolution rather than precedential command.
Some of the Justices who adopted the clear-and-present-danger test in the 1930s and early 1940s might have wanted B and C as well as A. But some might have been surprised by the eventual slippage, and might have thought twice about supporting A—at least in its pure form, with no qualifying language—had they anticipated these results. In 1942, for instance, the Court still assumed that "lewd," "profane," and "obscene" speech was unprotected, and obscenity was at the time defined to include much sexually themed material that is protected today. As late as 1951, Justice Douglas, who eventually became a solid vote for protecting sexually themed speech, said that "obscenity and immorality" were "beyond the pale."
The slippage from A to B and C was not just the effect, identified by Frederick Schauer, of "linguistic imprecision" or "limited comprehension." Some of the Justices who voted for decisions B and C might have agreed that they were going beyond the boundaries that those who rendered decision A would have preferred. But the Justices would still have been willing to go beyond those boundaries, because they preferred B to A, and C to B.
Thus, a judge deciding whether to adopt proposed principle A may rightly worry that future judges, who have different understandings of equality or administrability than the original judge does, might deliberately broaden A to B. And there is little that the original judge can do when adopting A to reliably prevent this broadening; for instance, saying "But this decision should not lead to B" in the opinion justifying A may have only a limited effect on future decisions, since judges who prefer B to A on equality or administrability grounds may not be swayed much by such a statement.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
The slippery slope begins when the "abundance of caution" inverts from restricting the government's ability to revoke a general right "in just this case" to inciting a government to restrict that right. This applies to the second amendment as well as the first.
Slide into Chinese Commie Social Desitability Scores. Buy work boots, increase the score. Buy a video game, decrease the score. Try to rent an apartment, score is too low. Try to buy a train ticket, score is too low.
I would like a database of lawyers. No services or products to anyone on the database, not even medical care or groceries. They are 1000 times more toxic than organized crime.
How about keeping it simple? The purpose of government is physical safety. Stay out of feelings.
Government is allowing millions of violent crimes. Financial crime is physical because it takes away the result of labor. Specialize in safety, get better at it. Stay away from feelings. That is not a controversial aspect of government.
"The purpose of government is physical safety."
In what meaning of purpose? Enforcing? No. Defining? Maybe.
For example, I can see a governmental (group action) need for defining the rules of the road so that all drivers can 'know' what the expected behavior of others is (what side to drive on, who has precedence in certain situations, what a red light, yellow light, green light (and arrows) 'mean'. That is, defining the protocol.
At what point does a government get into enforcing compliance with the protocol is a whole different part of 'purpose.' Should they only cite after a violation leads to a loss (accident)? Or cite pre-emptively (protocol violation in the absence of damage is still a 'crime')? Big difference in 'purpose', incentives, and ability to infringe on rights.
Each of those steps should be proven safe and effective, in scientifically valid experiments. For example, use a case control method. Remove all traffic signs in one area. Heavily place traffic signs with automated enforcement, 100% of the time by traffic cameras. A year later count all the accidents in each location. Prove a meaningful difference justifying cost and pain to the public. For example, many hideous deaths by crushing result from the removal of traffic signs. No one will then resent signs and cameras. They know they will be safe from death by crushing. Post the result of the removal of signs with graphic crushing injuries on billboards.
One can do that retrospectively by finding locations matched across many factors, and compare rates without doing the prospective experiment.
Two prime examples of slippery slope / precedent morphing from an absolute prohibition in 5A into precedent giving government permission to do what is prohibited
Kelo - takings
Gamble - double jeopardy
Judge Kosinski persuaded me Kelo was good. When you have a publicly owned highway, who uses it? Profit making, private trucking companies. What is the difference with Kelo then?
Kelo also refers to property, not to real property. Chattel is covered. It could be the vehicle to seize corpses, and to end the 50000 deaths a year of people waiting for transplants.
I still am against public use simply being to raise tax revenue. Water, sewer, road, pipeline (infrastructure) for use by private and public individuals is one thing. 'Simply' trying to goose more tax revenue? Not so much.
What do you think of the seizure of corpses against the wishes of the family to save 50000 transplant recipients? For now, they are going to feed worms, which is crazy. As a compromise, make all corpses, presumptively donated, with objecting families having to block the donation in court after justifying it objectively.
Neither of those started with an absolute prohibition.
I've been sounding an early warning about this for at least five years now.
"Oh, look at the brain scan. You can see this change here in response to harrassment. That's physical, so ban it!"
Do not allow the weasels in service to dictatorship immemorial to do things like this. The purpose of speech is to have an effect on the behavior of others. It's just re-wrapping dictator patter that some things the people cannot hear unmediated by government, who is looking out for them.
Last year, we just went through the transparently bogus exercise of reviewing "the marketplace of ideas" in order to submit harrassment wasn't of value, and therefore bannable
In that case, as in brain scans oh look how awful he feels, the benefit of the First Amendment isn't that there's value in every drooling from some yokel's mouth. It's in denying nascent dictators their best club in the Golf Bag 4 Tyrants .
Exercise for Krayt: show how allowing a nascent dictator free use of, "Kike," is more beneficial than banning, "Kike," for everyone. Assume for the sake of your reply that everyone who wants to use that word in a discussion like this one gets an exception, for, "fair use."
What about as transparency for what the speaker is 'really' thinking? By banning certain words and symbols, we are thereby leading to 'code' words, 'dog whistles' and misunderstanding when different people use 'trap house' in different contexts.
All responses are brain based, and involve chemical and physical effects. There is no evidence such a consequence is damaging. It may be beneficial, by causing maturity and growth. Maybe the victim should be made to pay for this benefit.
Typographic note: "Judicial-Judicial" gets an N-dash, not a hyphen. Should be instead, "Judicial–Judicial." The general case is any two-sided expression where neither side modifies the other. Another example: "Labor–Management Relations." Contrast, "Un-ionized." In the last example, "Un," is talking about, "ionized," not co-existing with it as an equal.
In instances like those above, make N-dash use habitual. There are cases where you can actually change the meaning of a sentence if you choose a hyphen instead of an N-dash (today's puzzle, show such a case).
Another handy distinction: range of numbers, or range of dates, also should get N-dash, not hyphen. For instance, "During the WW II interval, 1939–1945." Not: "During the WW II interval, 1939-1945."
A third useful distinction. When using fonts which do not come with dedicated minus signs (most of them), use the N-Dash, not the M-dash, for your minus sign. Note this visual comparison, with N-dash shown first, and M-dash shown second: " + or – " vs, " + or —". See that the M-dash shown second is notably wider than the plus sign. It is usually better if the widths of plus signs and minus signs match, as they typically do when the N-dash is used for the minus sign.
I add spaces before/after the N-dash (e.g. During the WW II interval, 1939 – 1945. . .,), for readability.
Is that OK?
apedad — I think that is ideal, if you are using a typesetting program that allows you to kern those spaces smaller. Not sure what the New Yorker would say. Pretty sure most style guides do it my way, without the spaces, but I stopped being pickled in typography about 2002. I might even misremember, because the work I did in design-intensive typography bypassed style guides, in favor of hand kerning and visually-optimized everything.
Will comment every few posts.
My outlook makes me highly skeptiical of slippery slope argumejts. In a democratic, diverse society, legislation and policy largely consist of making compromises and drawing boundaries between competing risks and values.
Slippery slope arguments essentially argue that such compromises, and hence the democratic process itself, is impossible. But a democratic society has to assume that in general, such compromises and boundaries are possible. Otherwise the democratic legislative process isn’t possible.
Slippery slope arguments are essentially arguments that the other guy’s values are worthless and my values should always trump. If we listen to the other guy at all, next thing we know he’ll be getting his way completely.
For this reason, they are generally made by people in power who are confident of their power and perceive no need to listen to what the other guy says. Judges in courts, for example.
Because the democratic process assumes people are grown-up enough to make compromises and boundaries, I don’t think arguments that they can’t ought to have much place in constitutional analysis.
If we think the other guy’s opinion is worthless and shouldn’t count for anything, why not just say so? Why put up an intellectual-sounding smokescreen to hide what is basically a power grab?
ReaderY — One of your best comments.
Agree and will add the democratic process also allows a society to reverse direction too, e.g. Carter/Reagan-Bush/Clinton/Bush2/Obama/Trump/Biden, etc., if we go too far in one direction.
Of course this is at the tactical level and doesn't affect the 200+ year general trend of Progress in our country.
Nonsense. The slippery slope argument is a simple acknowledgement that sophistry and bad faith arguments exist and are what makes law differ from something like mathematics.
If I make arguments about rational numbers or integers to a mathematician, we both know exactly what we are discussing and can have an exact and good faith discussion about specifics because we are exact. We have objective methods and descriptions.
With law, rhetoric or anything more subjective, in many cases the honesty is lost. Rather than have honest enlightening discussions, Sarcastrian word games are played. Need a new definition of "white supremacist" to tar your opponent with ? Simply make one up ! Does the standard definition of racist present problems for your viewpoint ? Play Motte and Bailey games with that definition and redefine it. Really poor at actual argumentation ? Vapidly yell "Redbaiting !" or "Conspiracy !" to to avoid honest discussion. Really want to fund something and need a bit of propaganda to sell it ? Redefine what a public good is. We could go on here practically forever.
These sorts of dishonest things are the nature of the worst of us. It is not a question of devaluing the "values" of the other guy. It is the realization that dishonesty exists and is a major part of political discourse. In fact, if you are watching folks who up to the last couple of years could clearly define male and female suddenly lose the capacity to make that distinction, you are watching the slippery slope in action. It has little to do with values and much to do with the fact that not everyone is honest and rationalization rather than actual thinking rules the roost.
Isn’t saying the other guy is being dishonest just another way of saying the other guy is REALLY BAD and you shouldn’t listen to what the other guy has to say?
And if the other guy really is being dishonest, why not just say so? Why make this slippery slope argument?
Time to note again that EV's slippery slope discussions bear striking resemblance to a practice objected to by Franklin, which was to invoke rights as a means to disrupt discussions about them. For instance, would-be gun controller wants to discuss regulating guns as if they were vehicles, including universal licensing, registration, and insurance. Gun advocates chorus in response, "CONFISCATION! Our gun rights are unqualified. End of discussion."
Slippery slopes discussed by EV work similarly. A party with an eye to preserving a preferred status quo attempts to rule out discussion of alternatives, by citing some extreme counter-possibility, which is not under consideration. The point is not to promote reasoned debate. The point is to shut down reasoned debate.
" For instance, would-be gun controller wants to discuss regulating guns as if they were vehicles, including universal licensing, registration, and insurance."
Except the gun controllers never actually want to regulate guns as if they were vehicles.
With Vehicles:
1. Licensing is shall issue baring objective tests of skills/vision. A license is only needed to drive a vehicle on public roads. You can legally drive a vehicle on private land without a license.
2. Registration is not universal. You can legally own unregistered vehicles as long as you don't use them on public roads.
3. Mandatory insurance only covers your own damages and liability for negligence. It wouldn't cover liability for criminal misuse of a vehicle.
4. You can buy a vehicle without a license or a background check.
The above is never what the gun control advocates want when they talk about regulating guns like vehicles.
MatthewSlyfield — Good for you! You managed to have a discussion about a right without asserting the right is absolute. You avoided overturning the conference table.
Of course you did not realize that the would-be gun controller was talking about rules for a CDL with a school bus certification, as applied to school bus owner–operators. Both state and federal regulations apply. State regulations can vary. Everyone gets a background check, plus fingerprinting. Mandatory alcohol and drug testing up to 4 times per year, with surprise notifications. State inspectors get access to your bus yard, and inspect the equipment whenever they want. Annual physicals by state certified doctors, at your expense (twice-annual after age 70). That is before we talk about insurance.
Before you reply, remember we are just discussing rights. No kicking over the table, by claiming the right is absolute. Tell me, to balance accurately the public interest in each activity—public vehicle operation vs. public gun carrying—do you suppose the private vehicle standard is a better fit, or is the school bus standard a better fit?
"Of course you did not realize that the would-be gun controller was talking about rules for a CDL with a school bus certification, as applied to school bus owner–operators. Both state and federal regulations apply. State regulations can vary. Everyone gets a background check, plus fingerprinting."
And you move the goal posts.
"Before you reply, remember we are just discussing rights."
No, we are discussing the fact that your chosen gun regulation/vehicle regulation is entirely inapplicable towards supporting any gun control proposal that has ever been put on the table.
I have put that one on the table repeatedly, in previous comments. By the way, considering especially the concerns for public safety in each instance, which do you favor as the proper standard for comparison, private vehicles restricted to private property, or the school bus example?