The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The Court's Religious Discrimination Reasoning in the Masterpiece Cakeshop Case
Why did the Court find that Colorado acted based on hostility to religion -- and thus violated the Free Exercise Clause -- and not just based on hostility to sexual orientation discrimination?
The main question raised in Masterpiece Cakeshop had to do with the Free Speech Clause, and the prohibition on "compelled speech": Would requiring a baker to make a wedding cake for a same-sex wedding (even one without specific wording or symbolism, such as a rainbow design) be compelling the baker to engage in speech, and thus violate the First Amendment? As the Court put it, "Phillips … argues that he had to use his artistic skills to make an expressive statement, a wedding endorsement in his own voice and of his own creation," and "this contention has a significant First Amendment speech component."
But ultimately the Court focused on a different matter: In resolving this question under Colorado law (which past Colorado decisions had said "afforded storekeepers some latitude to decline to create specific messages the storekeeper considered offensive"), Colorado executive and judicial bodies—the Colorado Civil Rights Division, the Colorado Civil Rights Commission, and the Colorado Court of Appeals—appeared to be discriminating against Masterpiece Cakeshop because of its owner's religiosity. And this, the Court held, violated the Free Exercise Clause: While that Clause generally doesn't mandate exemptions from neutrally applied generally applicable laws, this law wasn't neutrally applied.
Why is that? The Court basically points to three elements.
First, the Court concludes,
The Civil Rights Commission's treatment of his case has some elements of a clear and impermissible hostility toward the sincere religious beliefs that motivated his objection.
That hostility surfaced at the Commission's formal, public hearings, as shown by the record. On May 30, 2014, the seven-member Commission convened publicly to consider Phillips' case. At several points during its meeting, commissioners endorsed the view that religious beliefs cannot legitimately be carried into the public sphere or commercial domain, implying that religious beliefs and persons are less than fully welcome in Colorado's business community. One commissioner suggested that Phillips can believe "what he wants to believe," but cannot act on his religious beliefs "if he decides to do business in the state." A few moments later, the commissioner restated the same position: "[I]f a businessman wants to do business in the state and he's got an issue with the—the law's impacting his personal belief system, he needs to look at being able to compromise."
Standing alone, these statements are susceptible of different interpretations. On the one hand, they might mean simply that a business cannot refuse to provide services based on sexual orientation, regardless of the proprietor's personal views. On the other hand, they might be seen as inappropriate and dismissive comments showing lack of due consideration for Phillips' free exercise rights and the dilemma he faced. In view of the comments that followed, the latter seems the more likely.
I think that it's hard to make much of these statements by themselves; they simply reflect the Court's holding in Employment Division v. Smith that "an individual's religious beliefs" do not "excuse him from compliance with an otherwise valid law." Indeed, under Smith, a person can believe "what he wants to believe," but cannot act on his religious beliefs—if those actions violate an otherwise valid law—"if he decides to do business," or even just decides to be present, "in the state."
But, second, the court pointed to a statement by one commissioner at a later Commission meeting:
On this occasion another commissioner made specific reference to the previous meeting's discussion but said far more to disparage Phillips' beliefs. The commissioner stated:
"I would also like to reiterate what we said in the hearing or the last meeting. Freedom of religion and religion has been used to justify all kinds of discrimination throughout history, whether it be slavery, whether it be the holocaust, whether it be—I mean, we—we can list hundreds of situations where freedom of religion has been used to justify discrimination. And to me it is one of the most despicable pieces of rhetoric that people can use to—to use their religion to hurt others."
To describe a man's faith as "one of the most despicable pieces of rhetoric that people can use" is to disparage his religion in at least two distinct ways: by describing it as despicable, and also by characterizing it as merely rhetorical—something insubstantial and even insincere. The commissioner even went so far as to compare Phillips' invocation of his sincerely held religious beliefs to defenses of slavery and the Holocaust. This sentiment is inappropriate for a Commission charged with the solemn responsibility of fair and neutral enforcement of Colorado's antidiscrimination law—a law that protects discrimination on the basis of religion as well as sexual orientation.
The record shows no objection to these comments from other commissioners. And the later state-court ruling reviewing the Commission's decision did not mention those comments, much less express concern with their content. Nor were the comments by the commissioners disavowed in the briefs filed in this Court. For these reasons, the Court cannot avoid the conclusion that these statements [by an adjudicatory body deciding a particular case] cast doubt on the fairness and impartiality of the Commission's adjudication of Phillips' case.
Here, the statement does seem more like hostility to a particular kind of religious belief, and not just hostility to a secularly defined practice (discrimination). The two are often hard to tease apart, but seven Justices were persuaded that this impermissible hostility to religion was present here.
And then the Court pointed to the third fact:
Another indication of hostility is the difference in treatment between Phillips' case and the cases of other bakers who objected to a requested cake on the basis of conscience and prevailed before the Commission…. [O]n at least three other occasions [all brought by one William Jack,] the Civil Rights Division considered the refusal of bakers to create cakes with images that conveyed disapproval of same-sex marriage, along with religious text. Each time, the Division found that the baker acted lawfully in refusing service. It made these determinations because, in the words of the Division, the requested cake included "wording and images [the baker] deemed derogatory," featured "language and images [the baker] deemed hateful," or displayed a message the baker "deemed as discriminatory, Jack v. Azucar Bakery.
The treatment of the conscience-based objections at issue in these three cases contrasts with the Commission's treatment of Phillips' objection.
The Commission ruled against Phillips in part on the theory that any message the requested wedding cake would carry would be attributed to the customer, not to the baker. Yet the Division did not address this point in any of the other cases with respect to the cakes depicting anti-gay marriage symbolism.
Additionally, the Division found no violation of CADA in the other cases in part because each bakery was willing to sell other products, including those depicting Christian themes, to the prospective customers. But the Commission dismissed Phillips' willingness to sell "birthday cakes, shower cakes, [and] cookies and brownies" to gay and lesbian customers as irrelevant.
The treatment of the other cases and Phillips' case could reasonably be interpreted as being inconsistent as to the question of whether speech is involved, quite apart from whether the cases should ultimately be distinguished. In short, the Commission's consideration of Phillips' religious objection did not accord with its treatment of these other objections.
Before the Colorado Court of Appeals, Phillips protested that this disparity in treatment reflected hostility on the part of the Commission toward his beliefs. He argued that the Commission had treated the other bakers' conscience-based objections as legitimate, but treated his as illegitimate—thus sitting in judgment of his religious beliefs themselves.
The Court of Appeals addressed the disparity only in passing and relegated its complete analysis of the issue to a footnote. There, the court stated that "[t]his case is distinguishable from the Colorado Civil Rights Division's recent findings that [the other bakeries] in Denver did not discriminate against a Christian patron on the basis of his creed" when they refused to create the requested cakes. In those cases, the court continued, there was no impermissible discrimination because "the Division found that the bakeries … refuse[d] the patron's request … because of the offensive nature of the requested message."
A principled rationale for the difference in treatment of these two instances cannot be based on the government's own assessment of offensiveness. Just as "no official, high or petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion," it is not, as the Court has repeatedly held, the role of the State or its officials to prescribe what shall be offensive. The Colorado court's attempt to account for the difference in treatment elevates one view of what is offensive over another and itself sends a signal of official disapproval of Phillips' religious beliefs. The court's footnote does not, therefore, answer the baker's concern that the State's practice was to disfavor the religious basis of his objection.
Note that this too is complicated. As Justice Kagan, joined by Justice Breyer, noted,
What makes the state agencies' consideration yet more disquieting is that a proper basis for distinguishing the cases [i.e., a basis that didn't turn on whether the messages were "offensive"] was available—in fact, was obvious.
The Colorado Anti–Discrimination Act (CADA) makes it unlawful for a place of public accommodation to deny "the full and equal enjoyment" of goods and services to individuals based on certain characteristics, including sexual orientation and creed. The three bakers in the Jack cases did not violate that law. Jack requested them to make a cake (one denigrating gay people and same-sex marriage) that they would not have made for any customer. In refusing that request, the bakers did not single out Jack because of his religion, but instead treated him in the same way they would have treated anyone else—just as CADA requires.
By contrast, the same-sex couple in this case requested a wedding cake that Phillips would have made for an opposite-sex couple. In refusing that request, Phillips contravened CADA's demand that customers receive "the full and equal enjoyment" of public accommodations irrespective of their sexual orientation. The different outcomes in the Jack cases and the Phillips case could thus have been justified by a plain reading and neutral application of Colorado law—untainted by any bias against a religious belief.
So Justice Kagan thinks (and I agree) that there wouldn't be any evidence of religious discrimination if Colorado government officials had simply said, "The bakers in the William Jack cases were opposed solely to his anti-gay message, not to his religion; there is no reason to think they would have accepted a secular anti-gay cake while rejecting the religious one. Colorado statutes don't ban discrimination based on a person's general views on various subjects, but only discrimination based on religion, sexual orientation, and a few other factors. Those bakers actions thus didn't violate Colorado statutes, but Masterpiece Cakeshop's refusal to bake a cake simply because it would have been used in a same-sex ceremony, does violate Colorado statutes." But instead, the Court's majority concluded, those Colorado officials ended up drawing distinctions that seem to unconstitutionally turn on whether the officials view the messages as "offensive," and possibly on whether the baker's objections are religious.
Justice Ginsburg, joined by Justice Sotomayor, didn't think there was such discrimination, and therefore dissented:
[The William Jack cases and this one] are hardly comparable. The bakers would have refused to make a cake with Jack's requested message for any customer, regardless of his or her religion. And the bakers visited by Jack would have sold him any baked goods they would have sold anyone else. The bakeries' refusal to make Jack cakes of a kind they would not make for any customer scarcely resembles Phillips' refusal to serve Craig and Mullins: Phillips would not sell to Craig and Mullins, for no reason other than their sexual orientation, a cake of the kind he regularly sold to others. When a couple contacts a bakery for a wedding cake, the product they are seeking is a cake celebrating their wedding—not a cake celebrating heterosexual weddings or same-sex weddings—and that is the service Craig and Mullins were denied. Colorado, the Court does not gainsay, prohibits precisely the discrimination Craig and Mullins encountered. Jack, on the other hand, suffered no service refusal on the basis of his religion or any other protected characteristic. He was treated as any other customer would have been treated—no better, no worse.
The fact that Phillips might sell other cakes and cookies to gay and lesbian customers was irrelevant to the issue Craig and Mullins' case presented. What matters is that Phillips would not provide a good or service to a same-sex couple that he would provide to a heterosexual couple. In contrast, the other bakeries' sale of other goods to Christian customers was relevant: It shows that there were no goods the bakeries would sell to a non-Christian customer that they would refuse to sell to a Christian customer.
Nor was the Colorado Court of Appeals' "difference in treatment of these two instances … based on the government's own assessment of offensiveness." Phillips declined to make a cake he found offensive where the offensiveness of the product was determined solely by the identity of the customer requesting it. The three other bakeries declined to make cakes where their objection to the product was due to the demeaning message the requested product would literally display.
As the Court recognizes, a refusal "to design a special cake with words or images … might be different from a refusal to sell any cake at all." The Colorado Court of Appeals did not distinguish Phillips and the other three bakeries based simply on its or the Division's finding that messages in the cakes Jack requested were offensive while any message in a cake for Craig and Mullins was not. The Colorado court distinguished the cases on the ground that Craig and Mullins were denied service based on an aspect of their identity that the State chose to grant vigorous protection from discrimination. See [decision below] ("The Division found that the bakeries did not refuse [Jack's] request because of his creed, but rather because of the offensive nature of the requested message…. [T]here was no evidence that the bakeries based their decisions on [Jack's] religion … [whereas Phillips] discriminat[ed] on the basis of sexual orientation."). I do not read the Court to suggest that the Colorado Legislature's decision to include certain protected characteristics in CADA is an impermissible government prescription of what is and is not offensive….
Statements made at the Commission's public hearings on Phillips' case provide no firmer support for the Court's holding today. Whatever one may think of the statements in historical context, I see no reason why the comments of one or two Commissioners should be taken to overcome Phillips' refusal to sell a wedding cake to Craig and Mullins.
The proceedings involved several layers of independent decisionmaking, of which the Commission was but one. First, the Division had to find probable cause that Phillips violated CADA. Second, the ALJ entertained the parties' cross-motions for summary judgment. Third, the Commission heard Phillips' appeal. Fourth, after the Commission's ruling, the Colorado Court of Appeals considered the case de novo.
What prejudice infected the determinations of the adjudicators in the case before and after the Commission? The Court does not say. Phillips' case is thus far removed from the only precedent upon which the Court relies, Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah (1993), where the government action that violated a principle of religious neutrality implicated a sole decisionmaking body, the city council.
Finally, here is the argument from a brief written by Doug Laycock that the Court apparently viewed as quite influential; it might capture the majority's argument about the William Jack cases and this case better than the majority did:
The court of appeals rationalized this unequal treatment in a footnote. It said that petitioner's objection to the message he said his cake would send—his confessed "opposition to same-sex marriage"—discriminated against the same-sex couple that wanted him to send that message. The protected bakers also objected to "the offensive nature of the requested message," but the court said that refusing to make a cake with that message did not discriminate against the very conservative Christian requesting that message. The court of appeals reached this conclusion even though Colorado prohibits discrimination on the basis of "all aspects of religious beliefs, observances or practices … as well as the beliefs or teachings of a particular religion, church, denomination or sect.".
The protected bakers' willingness to produce cakes with other "Christian themes" for other Christian customers was treated as exonerating. Petitioner's willingness to produce other cakes and baked goods for respondents and other same-sex couples was treated as irrelevant.
For the protected bakers, the court assumed that the message would be the bakers' message and not the customer's; the bakers could lawfully object to "the offensive nature of the requested message." For petitioner, the court said that his cake would send no message, but if it did send one, it would be the customer's message, not the baker's..
For petitioner, the fact that he would merely be complying with the law meant that he would send no message. For the other bakers, this argument went unmentioned.
The court also said that in the cases it distinguished, the customer wanted objectionable words on the cake, and that in petitioner's discussion with the individual respondents he did not learn what they wanted on their cake. But petitioner could surely assume that they wanted some words or symbols on the cake, and an essential part of his task was to help them choose those words and symbols. In any event, the very purpose of a wedding cake is to celebrate the wedding and the marriage, with or without an inscription.
And under the court's reasoning, the case would have come out the same way even if the conversation had lasted longer and the couple had said they wanted two men in tuxedos, "David ? Charlie," a rainbow, or any other more explicit message. The court's logic would still have said that it would be the customer's message, not petitioner's; that petitioner would merely be doing what the law required; and that refusing to produce this message discriminated on the basis of sexual orientation.
Even if the court's alleged distinctions were more persuasive, and even if they succeeded in placing the two sets of bakers in different doctrinal categories under state law, that would not change the bottom line. The conscience of bakers who support same-sex marriage, or refuse to oppose same-sex marriage, is protected. The conscience of bakers who object to same-sex marriage is not protected.
This discrimination is like the ordinance in R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul (1992), where racial epithets were illegal, but "racist," "bigot," and a vast range of other offensive epithets were permitted. State law placed the two sets of epithets in different doctrinal categories, and the correlation between epithets hurled and speakers regulated was imperfect. But these distinctions could not save a regime that effectively "license[d] one side of a debate to fight freestyle, while requiring the other to follow Marquis of Queensberry rules." It is no more defensible here to allow one side to follow the dictates of conscience while requiring the other side to submit its conscience to the demands of any customer who walks in the door.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
"By contrast, the same-sex couple in this case requested a wedding cake that Phillips would have made for an opposite-sex couple. In refusing that request, Phillips contravened CADA's demand that customers receive "the full and equal enjoyment" of public accommodations irrespective of their sexual orientation. The different outcomes in the Jack cases and the Phillips case could thus have been justified by a plain reading and neutral application of Colorado law?untainted by any bias against a religious belief."
And Kagan uses the same disingenuous argument that homosexual activists have been using for years. No, Phillips would NOT have made the the wedding cake for an opposite sex couple, if that wedding cake was to be used in a same-sex marriage ceremony. Homosexuals always had the same rights as heterosexuals, to marry one person of the opposite sex. The fact that their legal entitlement didn't practically work for them doesn't change that fact.
Pretty much by definition, an opposite-sex couple wouldn't be ordering their wedding cake to be used in a same-sex marriage ceremony.
Why not? People order and pick up wedding cakes for other people all the time.
"[A] wedding cake [...] for an opposite-sex couple" is shorthand for the identity of the couple getting married, not who ordered or picked up the cake.
That would be wrong even as to this particular case, Josh R. According to the reports, the plaintiff's mother came in the next day at attempted to order the cake for the same ceremony. The mother was clearly part of an opposite-sex couple. The baker refused.
Stop the disingenuous nonsense. As I said above, "a wedding cake for an opposite-sex couple" is shorthand for the identity of the couple getting married, not who ordered the cake.
Would the baker have refused to make a wedding cake for a homosexual customer entering into a normal marriage?
Harmful and vindictive speculation, that is. Why on earth would anybody come into a bakery and order a cake while going over their sexual history ??? I would throw them out for disturbing the other customers.
For someone asking others to "Stop the disingenuous nonsense", maybe you should take your own advice. What you said above was not "a wedding cake for an opposite-sex couple".
This is dumb. Everyone understands anti-discrimination laws that protect homosexuals as being intended to force bakers to sell cakes for gay weddings. You may think that's a bad law (as do I), but we don't have to torture the anti-discrimination law until it confesses to being narrower than intended. I'll bake a cake for any black couple that wants to get married but not for an interracial marriage is still going to be discrimination on the basis of race. And if it isn't, every state with an anti-discrimination law would simply amend to make that clearer.
No, I don't think that's what the anti-discrimination laws were intended to protect. They were intended to protect them from being kicked out of apartments or jobs. Not to force someone to make them a "wedding" cake. And I don't think refusing to bake a cake for an interracial marriage is necessarily discrimination on the basis of race, unless certain interrace marriages are allowed and some not.
Just quoting this, nothing more to say here.
Whatever the result of such a case it is irrelevant to this case.
A homosexual inter-racial 'marriage' would be objected by Jack without any need to justify on what grounds.
You act as if these things are common.
I won't defend that argument. THe law does not demand compliance by conscience, that is the great objection of Alito and Thomas
the case "provides a stark reminder" of the consequences of the same-sex marriage decision. By choosing to endorse "a novel constitutional right over the religious liberty interests explicitly protected in the First Amendment, and by doing so undemocratically, the court has created a problem that only it can fix," they said. "Until then, Obergefell will continue to have ruinous consequences for religious liberty."
SLAVERY was exaclty the same case as Lincoln clearly saw
". Demanding what they do, and for the reason they do, they can voluntarily stop nowhere short of this consummation. Holding, as they do, that slavery is morally right, and socially elevating, they cannot cease to demand a full national recognition of it, as a legal right, and a social blessing."
Homosexuals always had the same rights as heterosexuals, to marry one person of the opposite sex.
That argument was lost a long time ago.
Not really. It was ignored by people set to create a "right" out of thin air.
You do realize Obergefell makes prohibitions on plural marriage unConstitutional because it didn't take the easy way out that everyone is entitled to marry one person of the opposite sex regardless of sexual orientation?? In fact Kennedy lends support for plural marriage by clearly directing "animus" at Muslims that practice plural marriage with his language in his opinion.
So an intellectually honest judge should rule prohibitions on plural marriage unConstituional which should set in motion the reforms the LGBT movement should have always been focused on?deconstructing the advantages of hetero marriage in such a way non married people get benefits like leaving a pension to one person they care about or simply getting rid of pensions in favor of a 401k.
"You do realize Obergefell makes prohibitions on plural marriage unConstitutional..."
He doesn't realize that because it isn't true.
Wow, I can feel your animus for Muslims that practice polygamy through the Internet!
I'd even argue that Obergefell made the 'discrimination' issue worse. Before, you could make the case that marriage was tailored to solving the whole children thing. Maybe not perfectly/narrowly tailored, but still reasonably so.
Now... the government gives huge benefits to two sexual lifestyles and ignores all the rest. Then flip it around, it discriminates against those sexual lifestyles by forcing them to 'pay for' the benefits given to hetro- and homo-sexual couples.
100% agree. The LGBT movement only cares about jamming their agenda down the throat of a society that historically discriminated against them but in 2018 LGBT adults have it better than 99% of Americans. Hetero American women?can't live with 'em...pass the beer nuts.
Their goal is to destroy the family.
"jamming their agenda down the throat"
No thread on this topic is complete unless someone uses this metaphor.
I agree with Eugene and Kagan that the Commission could have easily distinguished the Phillips and Jack cases without violating Free Exercise:
My only issue with the above quote is it didn't come from Kagan. I'm guessing they are Eugene's words and people may think he is quoting Kagan.
Instead, Kagan offered a different rational in response to Gorsuch's claim that Free Exercise categorically demanded that Phillips and Jack have the same outcomes (ether they both get their cakes or they both do not). Kagan claimed Gorsuch's reasoning was based on assuming the product was a "same-sex wedding cake" rather than a "wedding cake." She may or may not have a point, but Eugene's argument is better.
I should have included Gorsuch's words that Eugene persuasively countered:
Gorsuch improperly thinks the Jack would-be bakers objected to religious opposition to same-sex marriage rather than opposition (religious or secular) to same-sex marriage.
But the Founders would say, It is inherently wrong to pursue a legal ruling to the point of the conscience and interior of the litigant.
Gorsuch is wrong but you are wronger. It is no one's business to grill Jack as to whether he objects based on moral or religous or whatever grounds. You would deprive the atheist conscientous objector of all standing.
But in the case of the Jack case, specific scripture was being turned down when other scripture was allowed. So Jack's cake can't just a "scripture" cake. If it quotes John 3:16, do you really think it would have been turned away? The cake order that specifically quoted scripture quoted Leviticus. So Jack's cake involved individual judgement by the baker's - and that is judgement we do and should allow.
Kagan, in her construction is inserting a personal value judgement for proper judicial deference to individual's protected rights that she herself signed onto in the original Obergefell decision. I don't recall her dissenting to Kennedy's very clear statements regarding this sort of issue in that opinion.
SHe also was clueless about the danger referred to by Alito and Thomas that Obergefell is necessarilly going to collide with religoius freedom, with expression, with separation of Church and state.
Writing for himself and Alito, Thomas said that the court's decision "enables courts and governments to brand religious adherents who believe that marriage is between one man and one woman as bigots, making their religious liberty concerns that much easier to dismiss."
Utterly irrefutable.
Like Lincoln and slavery ...". Demanding what they do, and for the reason they do, they can voluntarily stop nowhere short of this consummation. Holding, as they do, that slavery is morally right, and socially elevating, they cannot cease to demand a full national recognition of it, as a legal right, and a social blessing."
"And to me it is one of the most despicable pieces of rhetoric that people can use to?to use their religion to hurt others."
It is absurd to believe that this sentence shows hostility to religion in general.
"It is one of the most despicable things a cop can do - shooting an unarmed suspect in the back."
Does that show animus towards all police officers? No. It shows bias against police officers who shoot unarmed suspects in the back.
This ruling is a joke.
Didn't bother to actually read the ruling, did you. Your comparison is a crude and highly inaccurate parody of what the Justices actually said.
You have to look at the META analogy to see the hostility. Making that "shooting an unarmed person in the back" when the officer being held up for the analogy is being reviewed for a minor administrative incident not involving physical harm would tend to show some animus, in my opinion.
Simply put: comparing someone's defense of their beliefs to supporters of the holocaust is so overboard as to reveal something about the speaker.
It's not about hostility to religion in general, it's hostility to the specific religious beliefs of these particular people because it reduces the bakers' sincere religious beliefs to an instrumental one intended to harmful ends.
As Newman and Sayers said famously, to believe is to believe something. You are one of those who say belief is good no matter what you believe or don't. But that is not the Christian or Jewish way, nor did the classical philosopers except for the Sophists argue that way.
Belief in marriage of man and woman is necessarily not belief in marriage of man and dog, for example What applies to everything applies to nothing . The Founders would not even consider another person deciding upon whether that belief was instrumental.
Jason, you hate and you seek a rationale.
Most people think homosexual behavior is wrong and perverse. THe law does not demand the change of mind you want, that people call it an actual good.
During slavery , you would have defended the worst of slave owners by the same argument.
But Lincoln had your number :
. Demanding what they do, and for the reason they do, they can voluntarily stop nowhere short of this consummation. Holding, as they do, that slavery is morally right, and socially elevating, they cannot cease to demand a full national recognition of it, as a legal right, and a social blessing.
So if a baker can refuse to sell baked goods, can a grocery store refuse to sell milk and eggs? Can a restaurant refuse to provide a steak and hashbrowns to an interracial wedding party? A hotel refusing to rent rooms to a wedding party?
The argument that this was different rested entirely on an assertion that was plainly contradicted by the facts of the case. He didn't refuse to design and make a custom cake, he refused to sell them any "wedding" themed cake, including several pre-designed options.
His refusal was on the basis of who they were, not what they were asking him to do. It was always a bad set of facts to make the free-speech argument.
I think what happened is you got 3 guys in a room that like drama and
Should have said? drama [sing it] happened!
They should be allowed to, yes!
He offered to sell them other varieties of cakes, including undecorated ones, and let them decorate them however they wanted. Incidentally, he also refused to sell a heterosexual person a same-sex wedding cake.
Where do you get that he refused to sell anything "wedding themed including pre-designed options"? Neither side made that claim in their court filings that I can see.
The answer is: we don't know. The Court punted most of the issue and just said that minimally that he's got the right to a commission proceeding that is neutral towards religion.
In a law court you would be crushed in seconds because in 250 years you couldn't produce one case of a store refusing to sell milk and eggs.
Free speech is the obvious and only answer here. You are the one saying on the basis of who they were. He simply says he can't be part of coerced support for homosexual behavior. Why can't you see that.
If he knew a customer was homosexual and they asked for a cake, he would sell them one. You make all about the gays but that is the opposite of his statement of the case and of the 22 state attorney generals petitioning on his behalf.
There is an underlying difference of opinion with regards to what exactly is religion or a religious decision. If religion is diminished to something as mundane as a decision to join the Elks as opposed to the Moose Lodge, then religion will always be of minimal protective value. If religion has the importance that it has had through centuries, and at the founding of this country, then religion and religious values will be protected.
The language of levels of scrutiny is sometimes controversial. Race is dejure a violation. Sex never had the scrutiny of race. Sexual orientation is a branch/redefinition of sex. There is a desire to make sexual orientation at the same level of race. At the same time, there is a movement to make religion merely rational. The hierarchy of the grounds for discrimination is where the "battle lines " are drawn.
If religion is relegated to the position of being something that is only allowed on certain days inside certain approved four walls designated as houses of worship or behind the closed doors of your house (potentially curtilage) then religion is meaningless. It is disingenuous to believe that there are not active hostilities to the notion of religion and individuals expressing religion.
What a bunch of blather.
Religion does not grant someone a license to ignore laws which all business must adhere to. By acquiring a business license, they agreed to be bound by Colorado laws.
If they don't like that, they can close their business down and admit they have no intention of following the same laws as everyone else, because they believe their (self) righteousness places them above anti-discrimination laws.
What's a "business license?" Are you suggesting that any person can be forced to waive all of his Constitutional rights through the licensing process?
Consider the question begged.
Sigh. Where do people come up with this stuff? It's completely wrong. First, they didn't agree to any such thing. Second, they weren't asked to agree to any such thing; that's not even what a "business license is." A business license is just a tax that some municipalities impose on starting a business. Third, following laws is not a matter of "agreement" in the first place; whether they agree or not, they are bound by the laws, unless some higher law governs.
And the number of legal minds that have followed just that course is quite big, starting with Corwin's
The "higher Law" Background of American Constitutional Law
Book by Edward Samuel Corwin
All you said is , you are bound by a law except when you aren't
We start with presumed innocence
It is the law not to discriminate on the basis of a person's religion. Religion has been a part of every discrimination an civil rights law.
I still say gays (and those who are not bigoted toward gays) should form a church, make gay marriage a sacrament, and fight fire with fire.
They better have guards at the entrances to the bathrooms.
You mean that thing people do before brunch?
Seems fair. But then again that keeps the question of the state siding for some religious beliefs and against others in bounds.
But that is not the issue. Neither side can change the other's belief. THe whole question is, Can I force you to put a pro-gay statement on your cake? NO, you can't.
Do you have teenagers. THey often do such things with absolutely no commitment to either side. If it were forbidden or even taboo to be religious they would try to force a cake with a religous message. You give way to much credit to people you don't even know. 🙂
Yeah,well ignorance of the law will make people suggest hateful dumb strategies like that 🙂
In what way is that a church when you admit (unknowingly) it has no basis but promote homosexual behavior. makes me laugh
It is the law not to make religion an issue if the contesting parties don't. Does it really make a difference if an atheist says "Gay behavior is perverse so I won't be part of it"
People like you will slowly and surely turn the great mass of people against what you are obviously supporting. Like the atheist who claims conscientous objection during war the issue is conscience not religion unless somebody like you wants to pervert things to make it an argument about what beliefs others are allowed to hold and why they can or cannot hold them
Jason, the ruling explicitly affirms that. You are tilting against something that is not even decided in the opinion.
Or to put it another way, you can believe both that
(1) Colorado has the right to place anti-discirimation laws on businesses providing public accommodations
(2) Colorado has the obligation to ensure that the process that adjudicates claims of discrimination are neutral towards religion, neither favoring religion or non-religion and carried out without hostility towards religious claims. That doesn't mean they must rule in favor of religious claims, just that they must do so in a neutral and detached way that ought to just be the minimal expectation anyway.
Jason is right and you are wrong
You are defining one side as religious and the other as neutral, something the Founders loathed. And at any rate Colorado obviouslly did no such thing or even attempt to be fair. 22 states Attorneys Generals agree with me.
"The bakers in the William Jack cases were opposed solely to his anti-gay message, not to his religion; there is no reason to think they would have accepted a secular anti-gay cake while rejecting the religious one..."
Hmm. Can a lunch counter refuse to serve people who believe that humans evolved from apes, as long as they equally refuse to serve people whose disbelief is secular or religious?
Keep in mind in this case the state law forbids religious discrimination.
But the discriminiation is in who gets to call something 'religous' in the first place. Answer me, what do you make of Pro-Life Alliance of Gays and Lesbians. You will call that a religous objectino and then turn around and say the baker acting against a gay is religous. That only means you set yourself up as supreme judge and you rule by callling something religous and then ruling against it because you called it relilgous!! A stunning lace of self-awareness.
IN law school they teach you the utter futility of opposing a reality with a counter-factual. If the court case were actually about the lunch counter you would never argue against it by making up the baker case. So learn from that.
Anyway, you didn't think about your own counter-example (pun) because nobody asks for a sandwich with cream lettering saying "Man is only an ape"
THe Baker doesn't care what you think, that is clear. You are the one that thinks that is the issue but is not for either the baker or the customer !!!! THey wnat a CAKE not an opinion.
I think the court persuasively argued the question of whether religious objections give a right to discriminate in the negative. But at the same time backed away from Smith by clarifying that "neutral" means in fact not hostile at least, and that "generally applicable" means that there aren't bigger exceptions granted for others than for the religious objectors.
This suggests that Smith was not a watershed moment in first amendment law but one more piece of a complex puzzle which does not override what came before. Instead of a watershed moment we are left with the idea that religious exceptions are judged in context of other exceptions and that the laws must not be hostile.
I don't see how this ruling significantly injures antidiscrimination law but I do think it significantly advances religious liberty.
You learn in law school the fallacy of Ignoring the Common Cause. Maybe --- as I have personally witnessed many times -- a person sees that homosexual behavior and killing of babies is a moral horror and leads to a religous conversion. But to say that you are against X because you are a Catholic is to say that you don't accept any religiouis opinion you don't have. I say this all the time: What do you make of Pro-Life Alliance of Gays and Lesbians.
OR Seculars for Life who make the Supreme Court's case very plainly when they say in their literature:
Church
vs. State
41% never participate in prayer,
scripture study, or religious
education;
17% seldom or never attend religious
services; and
12% consider themselves unaffiliated
with religion.
Pro-choice people frequently claim
those trying to restrict abortion violate
the religious freedom of their fellow
citizens. But the pro-life position isn't
solely a religious one. Pew Research
Center's Religious Landscape Survey
finds that, of those who think abortion
should be illegal in all or most cases:
Millions of nonreligious Americans
oppose abortion, because abortion is a
human rights violation. Religious
freedom doesn't justify human rights VIOLATIONS
TWENTY ONE State attorney Generals disagree with this analysis
And I see three errors in the analysis anyway.
1) 99.9% of Americans have a strong hatred of sexual perversions.Child molestation, bestiality, necrophilia, etc. So the argument that homosexuality actually should be approved begs the question
2) Of course it is Free Exercise. My study of the FOunders revealed an almost unanimous opposition to basing what is legal on WHY or WHY NOT you do what you do. IF it's wrong and illegal that is the end of the matter. As it should be.
3) Kagan is naive in this case. Only someone like Kagan would automatically separate a person's faith from their morality !!! Kagan presided over a gay wedding but felt that made her better than other people.
THe world is in high horrors and two gays needing a cake is the biggest problem ? ABSURD