The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The First Amendment and Restrictions on Gathering Information by Drone
From Sixth Circuit Judge John Bush's very interesting opinion Friday respecting denial of rehearing en banc in Yoder v. Bowen:
This case involves an as-applied challenge to a Michigan law (the drone statute) that makes it illegal to "us[e] an unmanned vehicle or unmanned device that uses aerodynamic forces to achieve flight"—i.e., a drone—while "tak[ing] game or fish." Drone Deer Recovery, a plaintiff here, offers a service where it tracks downed animals using drones and then posts the location of the animals' carcasses online so hunters can more easily find their kill. The plaintiffs allege that the drone statute violates their First Amendment rights because it (1) is a content-based speech restriction, (2) violates the speech-inputs doctrine, and (3) unconstitutionally restricts their ability to engage in inherently expressive conduct. The panel rejected all three arguments and determined that the statute survived intermediate scrutiny.
{We have referred to a type of protected speech as "speech inputs," but it goes by different names in different jurisdictions. The Tenth Circuit, for example, has referred to it as "the protected creation of speech," and the Supreme Court has referred to it as "[s]peech in aid of" protected speech.}
I write separately because I have concerns about the panel's reasoning related to the speech-inputs doctrine. The Supreme Court has indicated that "heightened scrutiny"— something more than O'Brien intermediate scrutiny—applies when the government seeks to ban the means to create speech. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc. (2011) (noting that a Vermont statute banning the sale of certain pharmaceutical data effectively banned certain entities from speaking with physicians and pharmaceutical companies and was therefore subject to "heightened scrutiny").
For example, if a State enacted a statute banning the ownership of pens and paper, the statute would likely violate the First Amendment under the speech-inputs doctrine because it would restrict the ability to express thoughts through handwriting. Here, drone-obtained information may be analogous to pens and paper because it provides what the plaintiffs allege is a critical input needed for Drone Deer Recovery's speech to hunters. But the panel declined to apply Sorrell's more rigorous level of review.
The panel's error may be understandable given the confused state of the speech-inputs doctrine following Sorrell. After all, that case is far from a model of clarity. The words "heightened scrutiny" have sometimes been considered synonymous with "intermediate scrutiny." But Sorrell also tells us that the statute at issue in that case "enact[ed] content- and speaker-based restrictions on the sale, disclosure, and use of prescriber-identifying information." Content-based speech restrictions are normally subject to strict scrutiny. Meanwhile, Sorrell did not find the statute's content-based speech restriction to be dispositive and proceeds to apply Central Hudson's commercial speech test, which is an entirely different inquiry from strict or intermediate scrutiny….
Sorrell is also unclear in the degree to which a speech input needs to be restricted before the doctrine comes into play. On the one hand, it seems like banning all pens and paper would easily violate the doctrine because that would outlaw the handwritten word. By contrast, a restriction on the use of a specific chemical in printer ink might not because printer ink still remains readily available. But Sorrell does not give us any direction on how to distinguish between the two types of regulation.
And, as a third point of confusion, the Supreme Court has never clarified how exclusively dedicated to creating speech the input must be before it receives some level of scrutiny under the First Amendment. When technology may be employed for purposes other than the generation of speech, those other uses perhaps may attenuate the level of protection for speech associated with use of the technology. Is a drone a speech input? Is a microchip inside the drone that is vital to its functioning?
Sorrell leaves more questions than answers, and the panel only added to the confusion. The panel determined that drones are not speech inputs, and then applied intermediate scrutiny anyway. But if the drones are not speech inputs, then it's unclear why any level of scrutiny would apply
The panel seeks to distinguish this case from speech-inputs precedents because Drone Deer Recovery's speech is not political. But the alleged wrong from prohibiting drone usage does not depend on whether the speech is political. Rather, the constitutional violation from banning a speech input arises when the restriction effectively abolishes the speech altogether. It is one thing to say that business-related speech, once expressed, may have less First Amendment protection than political speech; it is quite another thing to deprive the speaker of the means for expressing its speech in the first place….
In Sorrell, the Supreme Court held that a Vermont statute "restrict[ing] the sale, disclosure, and use of pharmacy records that reveal the prescribing practices of individual doctors" was unconstitutional because it "imposed a restriction on access to information" that could be used "in aid of pharmaceutical marketing"—i.e., it limited access to a critical speech input for pharmaceutical marketing. That case involved a statute completely divorced from politics, yet the Court still applied the speech-inputs doctrine…. So the panel was mistaken to the extent that it sought to distinguish Sorrell based on the non-political nature of Drone Deer Recovery's speech.
{As an aside, I struggle to see how the panel's distinction between political speech and non-political speech would matter here, given that the drone statute seems to regulate political speech as well. The drone statute would appear to apply equally to political speech. For example, the law would also foil the speech of animal rights activists who want to track down felled game and use it to protest animal cruelty—a quintessential form of political speech.}
The panel also attempted to distinguish Sorrell because the law in that case was not content neutral, given that the Sorrell statute allowed prescribing information to be used for some purposes but not others. But the drone statute similarly restricts a speech input based on the content of its use. The law forbids employing drones to obtain and deliver the location of felled game. But the law allows drones to deliver any other kind of information. For example, the statute apparently does not prohibit using drones to obtain and deliver data about the number and types of trees, the location of trails, etc. The drone statute thus regulates the speech input based on the content of speech for which the information will be employed. This is a content-based regulation much like in Sorrell.
We thus must apply Sorrell to this case. But what is the standard that Sorrell requires us to apply? I believe, based on the speech-inputs doctrine, it may be a higher level of review than the panel applied.
The panel's rejection of the speech-inputs doctrine may portend a split between our circuit and the Fourth and Ninth Circuits. In an opinion that came down after the plaintiffs petitioned for rehearing en banc, the Ninth Circuit concluded that an ordinance banning observing sideshows (a form of reckless driving in an intersection) was unconstitutional because it inhibits "the process of creating a form of pure speech." Garcia v. Cnty. of Alameda (9th Cir. Sept. 4, 2025). The court explained that, even though observing a sideshow might be a restriction on conduct, it was entitled to First Amendment protection because it regulated "a predicate for … recording of those events," meaning that it essentially outlawed a speech-input. {The Supreme Court has held that newsgathering is protected under the First Amendment.} Meanwhile, the Fourth Circuit has held that a statute banning organizations from planting moles (i.e., undercover spies) in farms and slaughterhouses bans a speech input because it "prevents an undercover employee from publishing a critical article based on any notes she takes of documents or policies laid out in a breakroom."
The statutes in Garcia and PETA are a bit afield of the facts of this case, but the panel's reasoning may be difficult to square with those cases. If observing employees in a slaughterhouse or watching reckless drivers in an intersection are speech inputs governed by Sorrell, then it would appear that observing animals via a drone would also be such a speech input. To be sure, the panel might say PETA involved political speech because the plaintiff was an animal rights advocacy group. But the plaintiff in Garcia was a transportation reporter, and there is no indication from that case that he was engaged in political speech.
If this case began and ended as a hunting-with-drones precedent, it perhaps would not be worth delving so deeply into the panel's rationale for its decision. But I worry that the panel's opinion may be interpreted to diminish First Amendment protection more broadly, including for academics and journalists.
Consider how the panel's reasoning could be employed to diminish academic freedom. Many academic studies rely on recorded interviews. A State could theoretically enact a statute banning the recording of interviews between a healthcare provider and a patient. This prohibition would make it unlawful, for example, to use recorded interviews in a study examining whether psychologists can convince children to remember traumatic events that did not happen. Such a study could radically change the way we consider witness testimony in many criminal trials. And yet, employing reasoning similar to the panel's rationale here, a State's transparent attempt to stifle that research could be subject to mere O'Brien intermediate scrutiny because (1) a psychology paper is not political speech, and (2) the statute only restricts employment of a particular technology (a recording device) that can be analogized to the drone usage in this case.
The potential effects of the panel's reasoning could be similarly problematic for journalists. Consider a statute that bans audio or video recorded interviews altogether. If a journalist wanted to document, for example, eyewitness accounts of athletes who gambled on their own games, this statute would effectively ban that form of journalism that relates to a non-political topic. And yet, even though journalism (muckraking in particular) is one of the First Amendment's central concerns, a statute restricting these journalists' recordings would be subject only to O'Brien intermediate scrutiny simply because (1) the interview does not involve political speech and (2) the law did not ban the interview itself but only particular ways of recording the interview. Using the rationale advanced to defend the drone statute—that the drone statute only bans a particular technology to gather information but leaves in place traditional methods for tracking killed prey—one could argue that banning video and audio recordings of interviews is acceptable because the journalist can still use the traditional pen-and-paper method to memorialize those interviews.
These two hypotheticals cover academic research and journalism—areas that are supposed to receive the highest levels of First Amendment protection, even when they do not implicate political speech. See, e.g., Fla. Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.S. 524, 541 (1989) (applying strict scrutiny to statute limiting a journalist's ability to publish the name of a sexual assault victim); Keyishian v. Bd. of Regents (1967) ("Our Nation is deeply committed to safeguarding academic freedom, which is of transcendent value to all of us and not merely to the teachers concerned. That freedom is therefore a special concern of the First Amendment."). And yet, under the panel's reasoning, they may receive only O'Brien intermediate scrutiny—with significant consequences, indeed.
That said, although I have concerns about the panel's opinion, I do not think that this case is a viable candidate for rehearing en banc. The panel's reasoning stems from a difficult-to-interpret Supreme Court opinion, and we are powerless to modify the directives from a controlling Supreme Court opinion in any way. So all that is left to do is wait for further guidance from the Supreme Court.
I cannot blame the panel opinion for its attempt to sort through confusing Supreme Court precedent. After all, Sorrell appears to call for O'Brien intermediate scrutiny, strict scrutiny, and Central Hudson scrutiny, all at the same time. Thus, three people could theoretically argue in favor of each separate standard of review, and Sorrell would provide equally strong support for each position. But I am still concerned that the panel's reasoning in this case might cause problems down the road. Ultimately, I hope that the Supreme Court will give plenary consideration to this case or one like it to clarify the parameters of the speech-inputs doctrine.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
"For example, the law would also foil the speech of animal rights activists who want to track down felled game and use it to protest animal cruelty—a quintessential form of political speech."
No, the drone ban only applies to those who are out to "take game or fish".
I'm struggling to understand the 1A implications of this. Yes, Drone Deer Recovery publishes their findings, and if the law made it illegal to publish the locations of dead deer it would clearly violate 1A.
But that's not what the law does. In US v Stevens the court ruled that while laws prohibiting organized dog fights were constitutional, laws prohibiting the distribution of dog-fight videos are not.
Seems to me the same thing would apply here. Drone Deer Recovery is free to publish whatever they want, but that doesn't excuse illegal activity.
Am I missing something?
Drone Deer Recovery is potentially in a criminal conspiracy with hunters, or aiding and abetting them. If I redistribute a dog fight video I'm exercising my First Amendment rights. If I arrange a pay-per-view stream of an organized dog fight I'm in a different situation.
I follow what you are saying, but I was looking for someone to explain why Drone Deer Recovery might have a reasonable 1A argument. Cause I'm not seeing it.
Replace deer with ICE agents, and hunters with antifa and try again.
Keeping drones out of big game hunting is rational and necessary. An obvious hazard, amounting to a near-certainty, is that drones will be used to locate live game, and guide hunters to it.
My guess is that this case shows an example of that tactic being covered with a sketchy excuse. It seems inconceivable that any such operation to recover dead game which hunters failed to track could pay for itself by that activity alone. Too hard to organize. Too likely to fail.
But scouting for live game with drones? Easy to organize, and in some areas a likely bonanza—albeit one which sporting hunters would oppose, and fish and game departments would be unlikely to approve. Hence the need for a virtuous-looking pretext, however improbable.
The right way to deal with that problem is to ban all drone use in areas open to big game hunting, except in cases of public safety emergency, such as medical rescues.
Under the opinion, it would apear a peeping Tom statute is barred by the Frst Amendment. So long as they use cameras rather than their memory, prohibiting espionage generally might be unconstitutional. Indeed, every crime that involves creating a record of some kind as part of its commission becomes a strict scrutiny matter.
How can states constitutionally require a license to drive? Modern cars generate data, which is speech. You can’t require a license to generate speech. And the act of driving is as peripheral to the generation of data, as purely incidental to the constitutionally primary act of data (speech) generation, as the act of flying a drone in this case.
I’ll point out that technology permits converting essentially any activity into a form of speech generation. Prostitution can be videorecorded. Lotteries involve data. Etc. Anything currently subject to rational basis review can be made into a First Amendment issue and made subject to strict scrutiny.
ReaderY — Don't be impatient. That project is already going as fast as it can.
"Prostitution can be videorecorded."
See Vivid Entertainment v. Jonathan Fielding, 774 F.3d 566 (9th Cir. 2014), generally upholding a voter initiative requiring porn actors to wear condoms despite the filmmaker's desire to depict spontaneous condomless sex. "So condomless sex is not the relevant expression for First Amendment purposes; instead, the relevant expression is more generally the adult films’ erotic message."
I dunno, this kind of feels like fishing with hand grenades. I grew up in Wisconsin, where the ideal forms of fishing and hunting always included sport and sporting. No one expected to see a deer every day of the season, let alone bring home the kill every time. Deer camp was always a lot of fun regardless of who bagged what. A couple of guys sitting in an ice fishing shack didn't expect to catch something every time. It was quality time, and the loser of a card game would have to bring the beer and bourbon next time.
So what's up with this then? If hunting is a sport, then shouldn't it require the development of certain skills, such as the ability to track a wounded animal through the woods? Sport hunters who want to use technology like this seem a bit lazy and entitled to me. Having said that, I'll also say that hunters who are actually out for food should be given some deference, as there might be hungry children to provide for back home.