The Volokh Conspiracy
Mostly law professors | Sometimes contrarian | Often libertarian | Always independent
The Proposed "Compact for Academic Excellence in Higher Education" and the First Amendment
[1.] There's a lot going on in the Trump Administration's proposed "Compact," and there's a lot that we might want to ask about it. Some questions would have to do with whether particular demands (such as a tuition freeze or a 15% cap on foreign students or mandatory U.S. civics classes for foreign students) are a good idea. Some might be and some might not be. Some might have to do with the way that the Compact would rebalance power between universities and the federal government.
Some might have to do with whether particular demands (for instance, the requirement that universities require all applicants to take standardized admission tests) should be implemented top-down on a one-size-fits-all basis. The federal government may have the power to impose certain conditions on the recipients of government funds, but that doesn't mean that it necessarily should do so. This question of when conditions become excessive micromanagement perennially arises when it comes to government contracts and grants.
Some questions have to do with whether the Executive Branch can impose these conditions through just an announcement, whether this would require notice-and-comment regulatory rulemaking, or whether it would require express Congressional authorization. Similar questions have arisen in the past with regard to whether, for instance, Title IX should be understood to mandate university investigation of alleged sexual assault by students; whether it should be understood as mandating a preponderance-of-the-evidence standard in such situations rather than a clear-and-convincing-evidence; and other matters. In particular, the Compact seems to contemplate conditions on universities' "preferential treatment under the tax code," which I expect would likely require revisions to the tax code. But there too there have been controversies about where the Executive Branch has power to read provisions into tax exemption requirements that hadn't been expressly authorized by Congress (see, e.g., Bob Jones Univ. v. U.S. (1983)).
Still, I can at most note such matters—important as they are—since they aren't within my core area of expertise. So let me turn instead to the First Amendment problems posed by the Compact, which I am more knowledgeable about. I don't want to suggest that these are the most important issues, but that's where the light is best for me, so maybe I can find some keys there.
[2.] As a general matter, when the government is providing funding or other benefits for private parties' speech, it may not discriminate based on viewpoint. Thus, for instance, Rosenberger v. Rector (1995), held that when a university funds student newspapers, it can't exclude ones that convey religious viewpoints. The Court there expressly "reaffirmed the requirement of viewpoint neutrality in the Government's provision of financial benefits." Many other precedents say the same.
To be sure, the government may create programs for conveying its own preferred viewpoints. As Rust v. Sullivan (1991) noted, Congress can set up a National Endowment for Democracy without setting up a National Endowment for Communism. But the Court has distinguished such government speech, which the government can select based on viewpoint, from government programs that subsidize a diverse range of private speech, as in Rosenberger. To quote Rosenberger again,
[W]hen the government appropriates public funds to promote a particular policy of its own it is entitled to say what it wishes. When the government disburses public funds to private entities to convey a governmental message, it may take legitimate and appropriate steps to ensure that its message is neither garbled nor distorted by the grantee. It does not follow, however, … that viewpoint-based restrictions are proper when the [government] does not itself speak or subsidize transmittal of a message it favors but instead expends funds to encourage a diversity of views from private speakers.
Moreover, the government can't impose even viewpoint-neutral funding conditions that seek to restrict the recipient's speech using its own funds. Thus, in FCC v. League of Women Voters (1984), the Court struck down a law that barred editorializing by the recipients of public broadcasting subsidies. The Court acknowledged that the government could provide that federal funds can't be used to editorialize (that would be a viewpoint-neutralize restriction). But Congress can't provide that "a noncommercial educational station that receives only 1% of its overall income from [federal] grants is barred absolutely from all editorializing." It is unconstitutional for Congress to thus bar a partly federally subsidized station "from using even wholly private funds to finance its editorial activity."
[3.] In the Compact, the government isn't just awarding grants for promoting particular government-supported viewpoints, which both Democrat and Republican administrations have long done. Rather, it applies to a vast range of funding and benefit programs, such as "(i) access to student loans, grant programs, and federal contracts; (ii) funding for research directly or indirectly; (iii) approval of student and other visas in connection with university matriculation and instruction; and (iv) preferential treatment under the tax code." Indeed, when it comes to tax exemptions, Rosenberger expressly made clear that "Congress' choice to grant tax deductions" was subject to "the requirement of viewpoint neutrality"; and see also the similar holding in Matal v. Tam (2017) with regard to the nonmonetary benefit of trademark registration.
[a.] This suggests that the Compact's requirement that, as a condition of getting benefits, signatories must "commit themselves" "to transforming or abolishing institutional units that purposefully … belittle … conservative ideas" is unconstitutional: It targets particular viewpoints (those that "belittle … conservative ideas"), however vaguely defined those viewpoints may be.
[b.] I think the same is likely true about the demand that universities "shall adopt policies prohibiting incitement to violence, including calls for murder or genocide or support for entities designated by the U.S. government as terrorist organizations." To be sure, "incitement" may constitutionally be even criminalized outright, if it's limited to speech intended to and likely to produce imminent illegal action, which is to say action in the coming hours or days, as opposed to speech that advocates such action "at some indefinite future time." (See Brandenburg v. Ohio (1969) and Hess v. Indiana (1973).) But in context, that doesn't seem the likely meaning of the demand: After all, basically no speech in the U.S. involves advocacy of imminent genocide by the listeners (as opposed to calls for genocide at some indefinite future time), and even calls for murder on college campuses are almost invariably calls for violence at some indefinite future time.
Likewise, while "material support" for foreign terrorist organizations, in the sense of providing personnel, training, and the like, is constitutionally unprotected (see Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project (2010)), "support" in the lay sense—which is to say independent expression of endorsement of a terrorist organization's position or actions—remains constitutionally protected. Indeed, Holder several times stressed that the law upheld in that case "does not cover independent advocacy" supporting a foreign terrorist group's position.
So unless the "shall adopt policies prohibiting incitement to violence, including calls for murder or genocide or support for entities designated by the U.S. government as terrorist organizations" is read very narrowly indeed, this demand would require universities to suppress fully protected student speech. And even if a private university could suppress such speech on its own (simply because a private university isn't itself constrained by the First Amendment), the government can't pressure the university into engaging in suppression (see, e.g., NRA v. Vullo (2024)).
[c.] I also think the government can't demand that universities, as a condition of getting benefits, "pledge … screen out [foreign] students who demonstrate hostility to the United States, its allies, or its values."
The government likely can deny visas to prospective students based on their viewpoints; see Kleindienst v. Mandel (1972) (I oversimplify matters here somewhat). Whether the federal government can deport already-admitted people based on such speech is a separate matter, but it likely can reject them when they're just applying for a student visa.
But that's something the government can do itself, because of its special power over immigration. I don't think it can demand that universities, in exercising their own decisions about whom to associate with and whom to speak to, exclude foreign students based on the students' viewpoints.
[d.] The Compact also requires that universities receiving federal benefits "shall maintain institutional neutrality at all levels of their administration," including "all colleges, faculties, schools, departments, programs, centers, and institutes." This means "that all university employees, in their capacity as university representatives, will abstain from actions or speech relating to societal and political events except in cases in which external events have a direct impact upon the university." This expressly does not apply to "students, faculty, and staff" commenting "in their individual capacities, provided they do not purport to do so on behalf of the university or any of its sub-divisions."
This requirement, unlike the ones I discussed in items (a) to (c) above, is facially viewpoint-neutral; and I think the government could require that no federal funds be spent on ideological commentary by university departments. That would be much like the requirement, upheld in Regan v. Taxation with Representation (1983), that no tax-exempt contributions—which are in effect subsidized by the government through the charitable tax exemptions—be spent on advocacy for or against a candidate, or on substantial advocacy for or against legislation. To be sure, Regan involved only candidate- and legislation-related speech, not all ideological advocacy, but I think such a viewpoint-neutral requirement would be permissible even if it covers ideological advocacy more broadly.
But as I read the Compact, it contemplates that universities "abstain from … speech relating to societal and political events" even when such speech is paid for solely with their own funds (of which universities have plenty). And that's precisely the sort of broad condition on funding that the Court struck down in FCC v. League of Women Voters, when it held that the government couldn't use its subsidies to public broadcasters to prohibit all editorializing by the broadcasters (including editorializing paid for from other funds).
I appreciate the rationale the Compact offers for the mandate, quoting the President of Dartmouth:
Consider a student interested in majoring in a certain subject. Upon going to the department homepage to discover course offerings, the student is slapped in the face with an official statement excoriating his own political ideology. How comfortable would that student feel taking a class in that department? Our Principles of Institutional Restraint permit departments to issue public statements only on limited issues directly related to their academic expertise. Rather than publishing these proclamations on their homepages, departments must create new webpages specifically dedicated to public statements and endorsements. This ensures that departments promote their academic missions, not their social or political beliefs.
I generally support such ideological neutrality mandates for university administrations and departments myself as a policy matter, partly for this very reason. But whatever the value of institutional neutrality mandates as a means of promoting uninhibited discourse among students and faculty, I don't think that this value can justify suppressing speech by the universities themselves. And, as FCC v. League of Women Voters makes clear, that remains so even when the universities are receiving government money to support some of their operations.
[e.] The Compact also seems to broadly call for universities to promote a "broad spectrum of ideological viewpoints." As I'll be blogging this coming week, I have a forthcoming law journal article in which I argue that ideological diversity mandates are generally a bad idea and likely unconstitutional, even when they are imposed as a condition on access to government funding. This having been said, it's not completely clear whether the Compact outright demands enforceable viewpoint mandates (which the April letter to Harvard appears to have contemplated), or whether it sets forth viewpoint diversity as an aspirational goal, the way one might set "excellence," "openmindedness," and the like as an aspirational goal.
The Compact states, in relevant part, that funding recipients must "commit themselves to fostering a vibrant marketplace of ideas on campus," to engaging in a "rigorous, good faith, empirical assessment of a broad spectrum of viewpoints among faculty, students, and staff at all levels," to "sharing the results of such assessments with the public," and to "seek[ing] such a broad spectrum of viewpoints not just in the university as a whole, but within every field, department, school, and teaching unit." It also states that "A vibrant marketplace of ideas requires an intellectually open campus environment, with a broad spectrum of ideological viewpoints present and no single ideology dominant, both along political and other relevant lines." The question here, I think, will largely turn on how such a call for a vibrant marketplace of ideas and a broad spectrum of viewpoints will be operationalized.
[* * *]
In any event, these are just some tentative thoughts about some of the provisions; I look forward to seeing more discussion of the Compact in the months ahead.
Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Comments may only be edited within 5 minutes of posting. Report abuses.
Please
to post comments
Congress can solve the tuition problem tomorrow by refusing to guarantee student loans at any university that increases costs more than 2%, and hold for 20 years.
We were nickle-dimed into this situation over decades, where large annual increases were softened by easy loans, and we can gently unwind our way out of it the same way.
Whether or not that hobby horse could improve anything, it has nothing to do with the Trump/MAGA attack on private civic institutions.
Given that those civic institutions have been giving aid and comfort to America's enemies since at least the 1960s, it seems reasonable to attack them.
+1,000,000
On a different note, the "Compact" offers funding in exchange for certain goals.
But what of California Governor Newsom's threat to "Eliminate all funding for any California School" that signs such a compact?
How in practice is this any different that the same funding cuts that Trump was criticized for?
https://www.gov.ca.gov/2025/10/02/governor-newsom-no-state-funding-for-sell-out-universities/
How indeed? Funny, that.
To normal people, there is no difference. But I'm sure Blackman will be along soon to denounce Newsom as an enemy of the Constitution, and Bernstein will follow calling him an anti-Semite and demanding that the University of California be stripped of federal funds.
Just another fascist move by Trump.
You ain't seen nothing yet -- wait for the exit exams with civics questions...
Can we please keep this appropriately simple. Confine the question to private universities. Their cases can stand for the whole.
If, for instance, Harvard, decides it does not want to do anything required of it by Trump/MAGA executive order, then Harvard can tell Trump to pound sand. If anything which happens afterward might seem retaliatory to a jury, then Trump, and whoever cooperates with the apparent retaliation can be tried by the next administration and sent to jail if convicted.
I leave the choice of charges to the lawyers, to decide upon after review of the facts.
While they are at it, the lawyers ought to review what charges a grand jury might entertain against the justices who voted for Trump v. United States. I presume the oath-sworn justices are as responsible as anyone else to preserve and protect the 1A, and cannot be more privileged than anyone else to deprive Americans of its benefits under color of law.
Shocking, I know. But less shocking, it seems to me, than allowing Trump's reign of lawless political destruction to go forward step-by-unchecked-step. It is imperative to confront the Trump legal rebellion whole, lest it become an enduring pattern for American politics.
The destruction being wrought is the right yardstick to guide response. Insistence on measured legal process remains wrong, while it is conducted in slow reiterative steps, as more people are being killed arbitrarily, and half of the edifice of America's governance is blown to pieces.
Nobody supposes this Supreme Court would be similarly hesitant to act if the Executive abuses committed were done by a left-wing extremist administration. That is plain. It calls for public political response, to remind justices that such bias is not one of their empowerments. Where it licenses Constitutional overthrow, such bias is culpable.
That there is no law on the books to punish oath breaking remains an ongoing political blunder. If any such thing existed, that might have abated the current emergency. Does anyone suppose that the present Congress would act now to pass such a law, and use that to at least attempt a return to normal governance? Of course not, the ongoing emergency is the goal of more than half the Congress.
Without any other kind of cure, extreme-looking remedies may be the only appropriate response to extreme political crimes. Trump/MAGA practices those so recklessly that they threaten outcomes as horrid as the worst treason. Responses must be proportionate, or chaos threatens. Violence is the straightest route to chaos, so must be avoided.
By elimination, that means unusual political and legal tactics are all that remain. I think it's either that, or a patient wait for the Supreme Court to put a final seal on authoritarianism as America's replacement for the People's sovereignty.
One problem Stephen -- the Student Aid Act *still* has not yet been reauthorized, only funded. So Trump could end aid to ALL private IHEs and tell them to "blame Harvard."
And as to Biden Part Deux, I will be very surprised if Trump doesn't pardon both himself and everyone working for him as he leaves office. He made the mistake of not doing that before...
Some questions have to do with whether the Executive Branch can impose these conditions through just an announcement, whether this would require notice-and-comment regulatory rulemaking, or whether it would require express Congressional authorization.
Trump's history of erratic decisions which change the next day, his record of violating 15 trade treaties (some of which he had negotiated himself), and his generally volatile decision-making process, make any "agreements" signed per this compact pretty meaningless. Anyone who trusts Trump's signature here hasn't been paying attention.
The academic left is being given the same deal as Hamas -- surrender, or be destroyed.
🙂 🙂 🙂 🙂 🙂
Either one ends up in destruction.
Trump's campaign to destroy American universities is one of the worst things any President has done.
Our university system is a national treasure. To destroy it to satisfy some brainless RW fools is an absolutely catastrophic idea.
But you're putting up smiling emojis. What a jackass.
No, our universities were a national treasure when they admitted based on merit and taught science, mathematics, medicine, philosophy, languages, history, and other academic disciplines.
When they started admitting unqualified blacks and teaching gender studies, they ceased to be a national treasure.
Oh, and unqualified whites were OK? Now I know how you get edumacated.
Hey Eugene,
All these trees you talk about are part of a large and threatening forest. Does that not interest you at all?
Perhaps the forest you talk about is not a legal forest, and he is only talking about the legal trees.
You could always start your own blog, or even post your own comment.
Perhaps the forest you talk about is not a legal forest, and he is only talking about the legal trees.
Of course that's right. But the legal trees seem to me to be a minor part of the forest. Discussing them is interesting to EV, I suppose, but dodging issues of greater importance looks a lot like willful evasion to me.
Does the presumably libertarian EV really have no opinion as to whether the government should prescribe admissions rules, for example, rather than let the universities set their own.
Reading intelligent, informative, well-reasoned posts like this reminds me of why I visit the Volokh Conspiracy, and makes me wish that most of the other Conspirators, with their tedious, tendentious monomanias. would disappear.
Hey EV -- This is just a pledge that institutions can sign or not.
But what if Trump then issued an executive order saying that only degrees from institutions that had signed would be considered for Federal employment.
Or say that degrees would be ignored and all jobs would be filled by testing, alone.
Never happen. More likely that the jobs will be filled by unqualified cronies.