The Pomo Mind

Was the conservative intellectual Russell Kirk a postmodernist?

The Postmodern Imagination of Russell Kirk, by Gerald J. Russello, Columbia, Mo.: University of Missouri Press, 248 pages, $44.95

Toward the end of The Postmodern Imagination of Russell Kirk, the conservative scholar Gerald Russello insists, “The possible connections between…Kirk’s conservatism and postmodernism are more than a simple enemy-of-my-enemy stance toward liberalism.” His book makes a surprisingly strong case for that unlikely claim. But it also reinforces what is likely to be the reader’s first impression: that the lowest and surest common denominator between Russell Kirk, author of The Conservative Mind, and pomo theorists such as Jean-Francois Lyotard and Jean Baudrillard lies in their shared antagonism toward the Enlightenment and liberalism in all its forms.

Kirk, a 34-year-old professor of history at Michigan State when The Conservative Mind was published in 1953, is an icon to traditionalist conservatives, an eminence so holy that he “often has been the subject of undue adulation and hagiography,” as Russello admits. Even conservatives who don’t think of themselves as traditionalists often pay lip service to Kirk’s authority. Russello notes the irony in this: Kirk, who hated the first Gulf War in 1991 and was at most a lukewarm defender of capitalism, would find little in common with today’s hawkish, pro-growth right-wingers. But even before his death in 1994, Kirk the symbol had become uncoupled from Kirk the man—a very postmodern turn of events.

Still, Kirk doesn’t seem at first blush like a postmodern figure. Premodern would be more like it. Kirk assumed a “carefully crafted eighteenth-century persona,” says Russello, along with an “antiquated style of writing.” Even more than his style, his ideas echoed various dead white Anglo-Saxon males who defended established institutions of church and state. Postmodernists, by contrast, tend to embrace the marginal, the “Other,” and the genuinely or putatively oppressed, while condemning the “cultural hegemony” of men and institutions that Kirk admired. Moreover, whatever similarities there might be between postmodernism and Kirk’s attitudes toward liberalism, a more obvious benchmark for Kirk might be the sentimentally conservative side of the 19th-century Romantic movement. Kirk is in many ways a chip off the Walter Scott block, not only in his criticisms of progress and industrialism but in his predilection for things Gothic and medieval.

Certainly Kirk lacks many traits characteristic of postmodernists. Unlike them, he never evinced an obsession with theory, a keen interest in power relationships, a yen for the transgressive. But he did believe that America had entered a postmodern age, defined by the decay of classical liberalism, and Kirk was confident, as he wrote in National Review in 1982, that “the Post-Modern imagination stands ready to be captured. And the seemingly novel ideas and sentiments and modes may turn out, after all, to be received truths and institutions, well known to surviving conservatives.”

Defining postmodernism is a dodgy business, but Lyotard provides perhaps the best short encapsulation: “incredulity toward metanarratives,” or skepticism toward grand stories like the Enlightenment account of scientific and moral progress. Traditionalist conservatives in the vein of Russell Kirk may or may not share that incredulity—depending on whether Kirk’s belief that “society is a spiritual reality, possessing an eternal life” counts as a metanarrative—but they find rationalistic system building equally distasteful, fearing that it strips the mystery and feeling from life.

Following the classical liberal economist F.A. Hayek, libertarians might make common cause with Kirk and the postmodernists against what Hayek called “scientism,” the misapplication of the methods of the physical sciences to the ordering of human society. But postmodern and traditionalist critiques of objective reason and philosophical liberalism can easily be taken too far; after all, the pomo sociologist Michel Foucault’s rejection of the Enlightenment led him to endorse, for a time, Ayatollah Khomeini’s Islamic Revolution (though by the time of his death in 1984, Foucault had come to a more temperate perspective on the Enlightenment and commended Hayek to his students).

Postmodernists and traditionalists alike run the risk of putting their loathing of the Enlightenment ahead of their love for liberty or justice. Luckily, even at his most anti-modern, and despite the evidence Russello marshals, Kirk was no postmodern radical, and he never went as far as the most extreme postmodernists and anti-modern reactionaries—though his attacks on libertarians and classical liberals certainly do not help the cause of liberty, a cause to which Kirk professed some allegiance himself.

Russello is a lawyer by trade, but his credentials as a Kirkian are 24 carat. He is the editor of The University Bookman, a quarterly founded by Kirk and now published by the Russell Kirk Center. Russello’s book is outstanding in its insights into Kirk but often leaves something to be desired in its discussion of postmodernism. At times The Postmodern Imagination of Russell Kirk seems scattershot. It is drawn heavily from work that appeared earlier in conservative and legal journals—Modern Age, The American Journal of Jurisprudence, and The New Criterion, among others.

Instead of constructing a master narrative of Kirk as postmodernist, Russello makes discrete arguments in each of his chapters, which tackle by turns Kirk’s ideas about history, politics, and jurisprudence, and the general relationship between “Conservatism, Modernity, and the Postmodern.” The fragmentary nature of the book might seem appropriate for a text about postmodernism. But Kirk put a high premium on narrative integrity, and the intermittently persuasive case Russello builds for Kirk as a postmodern thinker would have been more forceful if he had approached it systematically.

Indeed, the book’s title notwithstanding, Russello’s best sections are those that have the least to do with postmodernism. The introduction and the first chapter, on Kirk’s “Life and Thought,” are a case in point. Russello usefully shows that Kirk’s conservatism was sui generis. Not only did it differ from the National Review conservatism that took root in the 1950s—which was shaped by the Cold War much more than Kirk’s own thinking was, and which at times savored too much of classical liberalism for Kirk’s taste—but Kirk’s conservatism was distinct from the Southern agrarianism of many of his friends and followers as well. Kirk admired Abraham Lincoln, for example, unlike those in the latter group, who see Lincoln as a tyrannical centralizer.

If Kirk had his differences with Cold War conservatives and agrarian traditionalists, he actively disliked neoconservatives and libertarians. Kirk called neocons an “endangered species” and famously declared, “not seldom has it seemed as if some eminent Neoconservatives mistook Tel Aviv for the capital of the United States.” He denounced libertarians in equally vehement terms. The “representative libertarian,” he claimed in a piece titled “A Dispassionate Assessment of Libertarians,” is “humorless, intolerant, self-righteous, badly schooled, and dull” and didn’t know “which sex he belonged to.” Kirk disdained classical liberalism in part because he believed it undermined its own religious and moral foundations. “The contract theory of society rested upon religious assumptions,” he asserted in The Conservative Mind, “and as religious faith decayed among the liberals…the economic competition and the spiritual isolation which resulted from the triumph of their ideals provoked among them a reaction in favor of powerful benevolent governments exercising compulsions.”

Yet Kirk admitted to a few areas of agreement with antistatists: “they do not believe that the United States should station garrisons throughout the world; no more do I,” he wrote in the same essay, and he found libertarian resistance to collectivism and centralization laudable. Russello looks only briefly at Kirk’s relationship to libertarianism. That’s a pity, since the question of why Kirk felt such animosity toward a group with which he had a good deal in common (in practice, if not in theory) is an interesting one, and his attitude could be fruitfully compared with the disdain many postmodernists feel for capitalism and classical liberalism.

Russello’s overview of Kirk’s politics is insightful, and his take on Kirk’s spiritual background is even more revealing. “Kirk did not have a particularly religious upbringing,” Russello notes, and indeed “his Mecosta relations had a reputation for being ‘spiritualists’ and for hosting séances and other ghostly summonings at their house.” Those formative experiences inspired in Kirk an early and lasting love for the Gothic and occult, which came through in his second career as a writer of horror stories. (Kirk’s top-selling book was not The Conservative Mind but his 1961 “Gothick tale” The Old House of Fear.) When he married in 1964, Kirk converted to Catholicism, but before that he described himself as a “Gothic Jew,” proclaiming “heterodoxy is my doxy, not orthodoxy.” Postmodernism at its best has a sense of the playful, and Kirk had a lifelong playfulness about spooks and hidden powers.

Still, all that sounds more like an old Romantic than a contemporary postmodernist. Russello begins laying his claim for a pomo Kirk in his second chapter, “Participant Knowledge and History.” There are three lines to Russello’s argument. First, Kirk “was in accord with the postmodern reluctance to propose grand statements about the ‘meaning of history.’ ” Second, “like the postmodernists, Kirk displayed a certain ‘presentism’ when speaking about the past”: He believed that living traditions in the present change the past, or at least transform how we conceptualize the past. Third, Kirk rejected the idea of entirely factual, objective history in favor of a belief in historians—and their readers—as participants in the construction of history. There’s some merit to all these threads, particularly the second one. Kirk, like the postmodernists, did see history as unfinished and imaginative, something that could not be understood by piling up facts in chronological order. But this understanding of history is not peculiar to postmodernists or to Russell Kirk, and few contemporary historians would find much to argue with in Russello’s other points. Who doesn’t recognize perfect objectivity as a chimera? And among today’s historians, who really believes history has an overarching “meaning”?

Elsewhere in the same chapter, Russello relates the dubious idea that Werner Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle in quantum physics, which Russello says “struck a terminal blow to the idea of scientific objectivity,” tells us something about historical knowledge. What does our inability to observe simultaneously the velocity and position of a subatomic particle have to do with our ability—or lack thereof—to understand what happened at, say, the Battle of Hastings? Even if there is uncertainty about both kinds of events, we are not talking about the same kind of uncertainty. We may not know whether King Harold was really killed by an arrow to the eye, but if he was, we can say with certainty that both the position and velocity of the arrow could have been observed simultaneously, if anyone had been in a position to do so.

Editor's Note: We invite comments and request that they be civil and on-topic. We do not moderate or assume any responsibility for comments, which are owned by the readers who post them. Comments do not represent the views of Reason.com or Reason Foundation. We reserve the right to delete any comment for any reason at any time. Report abuses.

  • ||

    Am I the only one who saw the title as the Porno mind?

  • ||

    Could someone explain to me post-modernism in a nut-shell for me? It's a concept that I can't really wrap my mind around...all I can figure out is that it has something to do with how reality is a social construct.

    And it's concepts makes great tv-shows.
    And shitty everything else.

  • ||

    Elsewhere in the same chapter, Russello relates the dubious idea that Werner Heisenberg's uncertainty principle in quantum physics, which Russello says "struck a terminal blow to the idea of scientific objectivity," tells us something about historical knowledge. What does our inability to observe simultaneously the velocity and position of a subatomic particle have to do with our ability-or lack thereof-to understand what happened at, say, the Battle of Hastings? Even if there is uncertainty about both kinds of events, we are not talking about the same kind of uncertainty. We may not know whether King Harold was really killed by an arrow to the eye, but if he was, we can say with certainty that both the position and velocity of the arrow could have been observed simultaneously, if anyone had been in a position to do so.

    Heisenberg's uncertainty principle proves that it is impossible to say with certainty the position and velocity of anything--an arrow, a planet or a galaxy. For a large object, like an arrow, the uncertainty is trivial, but exists nonetheless.

    The related dichotomy as to whether a photon or electron is a particle or a wave is trivial when applied to an arrow, but it still exists--even the arrow is both a solid and a wave.

  • ||

    It says a lot about the conservative "mind" that a wet fart like Kirk is considered any kind of thinker at all. As for "pomo," I say it's spinach, and I say to hell with it.

  • economist||

    Yeah, Kirk was kind of a douche.

  • ||

  • Someone Who Doesn\'t Want to L||

    Ana Luisa Stella,
    That doll singing video "INTERESTING DUCKLING SONG 2008" was terrifying.

  • Andrew Murphy||

    Russell Kirk was really a British Tory in America. He did a great job as a scholar of Burke and the 19th century British poets and writers but he over played his abuse of Liberalism. He thought all Liberals and libertarians were Benthemites when in fact Gladstone and Lord Acton were not only anti-Bentham but devout Christians. Likwise, Austrian economist libertarians like Ropke and Rustow were devout Catholics and had nothing to do with the utilitarianism.

  • ChiTown||

    Mr. McCarthy, You may already be familiar with it, but I might suggest considering Clinton Brand's essay in the Modern Age "50th Anniversary of the Conservative Mind" where he specifically encounters Kirk's thinking with an eye toward Gadamer. I'll have to pick up Russello's book, but it seems like you're correct that a wider discussion of Kirk vis-a-vis the libertarians needs to be written, though perhaps it already has. Quarrels with Frank Meyer, no?

  • nfl jerseys||

    vbrej

  • Nike Dunk Low||

    is good

  • sacs birkin hermes||

    That’s a pity

GET REASON MAGAZINE

Get Reason's print or digital edition before it’s posted online

  • Video Game Nation: How gaming is making America freer – and more fun.
  • Matt Welch: How the left turned against free speech.
  • Nothing Left to Cut? Congress can’t live within their means.
  • And much more.

SUBSCRIBE

advertisement